-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
Copy pathmarked-obj-tac.tex
664 lines (581 loc) · 42.5 KB
/
marked-obj-tac.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
\documentclass{tac}
% TAC style, 12 pp, Xy-pic ver 3.9, MikTeX version 3.2
\usepackage{amssymb}
\usepackage{hyperref}
\usepackage{mathtools}
\usepackage[all]{xy}
\usepackage{ifthen}
\usepackage{xargs}
\usepackage{bussproofs}
\hypersetup{colorlinks=true,linkcolor=blue}
\author{Valery Isaev}
\title{Model category of marked objects}
\copyrightyear{2016}
\keywords{Quillen model structures}
\amsclass{55U35}
\newcommand{\newref}[4][]{
\ifthenelse{\equal{#1}{}}{\newtheorem{h#2}[hthm]{#4}}{\newtheorem{h#2}{#4}[#1]}
\expandafter\newcommand\csname r#2\endcsname[1]{#3~\ref{#2:##1}}
\expandafter\newcommand\csname R#2\endcsname[1]{#4~\ref{#2:##1}}
\expandafter\newcommand\csname n#2\endcsname[1]{\ref{#2:##1}}
\newenvironmentx{#2}[2][1=,2=]{
\ifthenelse{\equal{##2}{}}{\begin{h#2}}{\begin{h#2}[##2]}
\ifthenelse{\equal{##1}{}}{}{\label{#2:##1}}
}{\end{h#2}}
}
\newref[section]{thm}{Theorem}{Theorem}
\newref{lem}{Lemma}{Lemma}
\newref{prop}{Proposition}{Proposition}
\newref{cor}{Corollary}{Corollary}
\newref{cond}{Condition}{Condition}
\newref{conj}{Conjecture}{Conjecture}
\theoremstyle{definition}
\newref{defn}{Definition}{Definition}
\theoremstyle{remark}
\newref{rem}{Remark}{Remark}
\newcommand{\red}{\Rightarrow}
\newcommand{\deq}{\equiv}
\newcommand{\repl}{:=}
\newcommand{\idtype}{\rightsquigarrow}
\newcommand{\cat}[1]{\mathbf{#1}}
\newcommand{\C}{\cat{C}}
\newcommand{\Cat}{\cat{Cat}}
\newcommand{\Mod}[1]{#1\text{-}\cat{Mod}}
\newcommand{\Set}{\cat{Set}}
\newcommand{\sSet}{\cat{sSet}}
\newcommand{\qcat}{\cat{qcat}}
\newcommand{\K}{$\mathcal{K}$}
\newcommand{\join}{\star}
\newcommand{\fjoin}{\diamond}
\newcommand{\Hom}{\mathrm{Hom}}
\newcommand{\Map}{\mathrm{Map}}
\newcommand{\Fun}{\mathrm{Fun}}
\newcommand{\colim}{\mathrm{colim}}
\newcommand{\we}{\mathcal{W}}
\newcommand{\I}{\mathrm{I}}
\newcommand{\J}{\mathrm{J}}
\newcommand{\class}[2]{#1\text{-}\mathrm{#2}}
\newcommand{\Icell}[1][\I]{\class{#1}{cell}}
\newcommand{\Icof}[1][\I]{\class{#1}{cof}}
\newcommand{\Iinj}[1][\I]{\class{#1}{inj}}
\newcommand{\Jinj}[1][]{\Iinj[\J#1]}
\newcommand{\Jcell}[1][]{\Icell[\J#1]}
\newcommand{\Jcof}[1][]{\Icof[\J#1]}
\numberwithin{figure}{section}
\newcommand{\pb}[1][dr]{\save*!/#1-1.2pc/#1:(-1,1)@^{|-}\restore}
\newcommand{\po}[1][dr]{\save*!/#1+1.2pc/#1:(1,-1)@^{|-}\restore}
\begin{document}
\maketitle
\begin{abstract}
For every functor $\mathcal{F} : \mathcal{K} \to \mathbf{C}$, where $\mathcal{K}$ is a small category and $\mathbf{C}$ is a model category which satisfies some mild hypotheses,
we define a model category $\mathbf{C}^m$ of $\mathcal{K}$-marked objects of $\mathbf{C}$.
We consider an application of this construction to the category of simplicial sets with the Joyal model structure.
Marked simplicial sets can be thought of as $(\infty,1)$-categories with some additional structure which depends on $\mathcal{F}$.
In particular, we construct a model category of quasi-categories which have limits of all diagrams of any given shape.
\end{abstract}
\section{Introduction}
Model categories, introduced in \cite{quillen}, are an important tool in homotopy theory and higher category theory.
For every model category $\C$ which satisfies some mild hypotheses and every functor $\mathcal{F} : \mathcal{K} \to \C$, we define a model category $\C^m$ of marked objects.
A marked object is an object of $\C$ in which some maps of the form $\mathcal{F}(K) \to X$ are marked (see \rdefn{marked-obj} for a precise definition).
If $\C$ is a category of simplicial sets with the Joyal model structure (see \cite{Joyal,lurie-topos})
and $\mathcal{K}$ is a set of objects of the form $\Delta^0 \join L$ for some simplicial set $L$,
then a marked simplicial set is a simplicial set in which some cones of some diagrams are marked.
The idea is that a cone should be marked if and only if it is a limit cone.
Of course, in general, this is might not hold, but we will construct a model structure on the category of marked simplicial sets in which fibrant objects have this property (see \rprop{mark-fib-obj}).
Moreover, every diagram of a given shape in a fibrant marked simplicial set has a limit.
Thus, this model category represents the $(\infty,1)$-category of $(\infty,1)$-categories in which limits of certain diagrams exist (and functors between $(\infty,1)$-categories that preserve them).
Of course, there is a dual model category of simplicial sets with marked cocones which represents the $(\infty,1)$-category of $(\infty,1)$-categories in which colimits of certain diagrams exist.
By choosing another category $\mathcal{K}$, it should be possible to construct model categories that represent $(\infty,1)$-categories of $(\infty,1)$-categories with other categorical structures,
such as the $(\infty,1)$-category of (locally) Cartesian closed $(\infty,1)$-categories.
We will not discuss such constructions in this paper.
In section~\ref{sec:marked}, we define categories of marked objects and prove some of their properties.
In section~\ref{sec:model-structure}, we construct model structures on categories of marked objects.
In section~\ref{sec:marked-simp-sets}, we consider a localization of a model category of marked simplicial sets and give a characterization of fibrant objects in this model category.
\section{Category of marked objects}
\label{sec:marked}
In this section for every combinatorial model category $\C$, we define a new model category $\C^m$ of marked objects of $\C$.
This model category is usually not useful by itself.
The idea is that we should take a left Bousfield localization of $\C^m$ to obtain an interesting model category.
We will show examples of this construction in the next section.
\begin{defn}[marked-obj]
Let $\C$ be a category, let $\mathcal{K}$ be a small category, and let $\mathcal{F} : \mathcal{K} \to \C$ be a functor.
A \emph{\K-marked object} of $\C$ is a pair $(X,\mathcal{E})$, where $X$ is an object of $\C$ and $\mathcal{E} : \mathcal{K}^{op} \to \Set$ is a subfunctor of $\Hom(\mathcal{F}(-),X)$.
Morphisms $f : \mathcal{F}(K) \to X$ that belong to $\mathcal{E}$ will be called \emph{marked}.
A morphism of marked objects is a morphism of the underlying objects that preserves marked morphisms.
The category of marked objects will be denoted by $\C^m$.
\end{defn}
We will sometimes omit mention of $\mathcal{F}$ and identify an object $K$ of $\mathcal{K}$ with its image in $\C$.
Let $S$ be a set of maps of the form $\mathcal{F}(K) \to X$.
Then we will write $GS : \mathcal{K}^{op} \to \Set$ for the subfunctor of $\Hom(\mathcal{F}(-),X)$ generated by $S$.
A map $f : \mathcal{F}(K) \to X$ belongs to $GS$ if and only if it factors as $\mathcal{F}(K) \xrightarrow{\mathcal{F}(k)} \mathcal{F}(K') \xrightarrow{f'} X$
for some $k : K \to K'$ and some $f' \in S$.
Forgetful functor $U : \C^m \to \C$ has a left adjoint $(-)^\flat : \C \to \C^m$ and a right adjoint $(-)^\sharp : \C \to \C^m$.
For every $X \in \C$, $X^\flat$ is the marked object in which no morphisms are marked (that is, $X^\flat = (X,\varnothing)$),
and $X^\sharp$ is the marked object in which all morphisms are marked (that is, $X^\sharp = (X,\coprod_{K \in \mathcal{K}} \Hom(K,X))$).
Objects of the form $X^\flat$ and of the form $X^\sharp$ will be called \emph{flat} and \emph{sharp} respectively.
Category $\C^m$ has the same limits and colimits as $\C$.
Let $D : J \to \C^m$ be a diagram.
Then underlying objects of $\lim(D)$ and $\colim(D)$ are a limit and a colimit of underlying objects in $\C$ respectively.
Morphism $K \to \lim(D)$ is marked if and only if morphism $K \to \lim(D) \to D_j$ is marked for every $j \in J$.
Morphism $K \to \colim(D)$ is marked if and only if it factors through some marked morphism $K \to D_j$.
\begin{prop}[mark-comb]
If $\C$ is locally presentable, then so is $\C^m$.
\end{prop}
\begin{proof}
First, let us prove that there exists a set of objects $S^m$ of $\C^m$ which generates the whole category under colimits.
Let $\lambda$ be a regular cardinal such that $\C$ is locally $\lambda$-presentable and for every $K \in \mathcal{K}$, $\mathcal{F}(K)$ is $\lambda$-presentable.
Let $S$ be a set of objects of $\C$ such that every object of $X$ is a $\lambda$-filtered colimit of objects from $S$.
Note that for every object $X$ of $\C$, there is only a set of marked objects $Y$ such that $U(Y) = X$.
Let $S^m$ be the set of objects $Y$ such that $U(Y) \in S$.
Let $X$ be a marked object, and let $D : J \to \C$ be a $\lambda$-filtered diagram such that $\colim(D) = U(X)$.
Then define diagram $D' : J \to \C^m$ so that $U(D'_j) = D_j$ and $f : K \to D_j$ is marked if and only if $K \xrightarrow{f} D_j \to \colim(D) = U(X)$ is marked.
To prove that $\colim(D') = X$, we need to show that $f : K \to U(X)$ is marked in $X$ only if it factors through some $D_j \to U(X)$.
But this follows from the fact that $D$ is $\lambda$-filtered and $K$ is $\lambda$-presentable.
Now, let us prove that every object of $\C^m$ is small.
Let $(X,\mathcal{E})$ be a marked object, and let $\lambda$ be a regular cardinal such that
for every $K \in \mathcal{K}$, $\mathcal{F}(K)$ is $\lambda$-presentable, $X$ is $\lambda$-presentable, and $|\mathcal{E}| < \lambda$.
Let $D : J \to \C^m$ be a $\lambda$-filtered diagram.
It is easy to see that $\colim_{j \in J} \Hom((X,\mathcal{E}), D_j) \to \Hom((X,\mathcal{E}), \colim_{j \in J} D_j)$ is injective.
Let us show that it is surjective.
Let $f : (X,\mathcal{E}) \to \colim_{j \in J} D_j$ be a map of marked objects.
Then $U(f)$ factors as $X \xrightarrow{g} U(D_j) \to \colim_{j \in J} U(D_j)$ for some $j$.
By the description of colimits that we gave above, for every marked $k : K \to X$, map $U(f) \circ k$ factors through some marked $h_k : K \to U(D_k)$.
Since $K$ is $\lambda$-presentable and maps $K \xrightarrow{h_k} U(D_k) \to \colim_{j \in J} U(D_j)$
and $K \xrightarrow{k} X \xrightarrow{g} U(D_j) \to \colim_{j \in J} U(D_j)$ are equal,
there exists an object $D'_k$ and maps $D_j \to D'_k$ and $D_k \to D'_k$ in the diagram such that
$K \xrightarrow{h_k} U(D_k) \to U(D'_k)$ and $K \xrightarrow{k} X \xrightarrow{g} U(D_j) \to U(D'_k)$ are also equal.
In particular, $K \xrightarrow{k} X \xrightarrow{g} U(D_j) \to U(D'_k)$ is marked.
Finally, since $D$ is $\lambda$-filtered and $|\mathcal{E}| < \lambda$, there exists an object $D_i$ together with maps $D'_k \to D_i$ for every $k$.
For every $k : K \to X$, map $K \xrightarrow{k} X \xrightarrow{g} U(D_j) \to U(D_i)$ is marked.
Hence, $X \xrightarrow{g} U(D_j) \to U(D_i)$ is a morphism of marked objects.
Thus $f : (X,\mathcal{E}) \to \colim_{j \in J} D_j$ factors through $D_i \to \colim_{j \in J} D_j$.
\end{proof}
Now, we assume that there is a structure of a model category on $\C$ such that every object in the image of $\mathcal{F}$ is cofibrant.
We will say that a map $f : X \to Y$ of marked objects is a \emph{cofibration} if and only if $U(f)$ is a cofibration in $\C$.
\begin{prop}
If $\I$ is a set of generating cofibrations of $\C$, then cofibrations of $\C^m$ are generated by the set $\I^m$ which consists of the following maps:
\begin{enumerate}
\item Map $i^\flat$ for every $i \in \I$.
\item Map $K^\flat \to (K, G \{ id : K \to K \})$ for every $K \in \mathcal{K}$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{prop}
\begin{proof}
Since every map in $\I^m$ is a cofibration and $U$ preserves colimits, $\Icof[\I^m]$ consists of cofibrations.
Let us show that every cofibration $f : X \to Y$ belongs to $\Icof[\I^m]$.
First, assume that $U(f)$ is an isomorphism.
Then $f$ is the following pushout:
\[ \xymatrix{ \coprod\limits_\mathcal{E} K^\flat \ar[r] \ar[d] & X \ar[d] \\
\coprod\limits_\mathcal{E} (K, G \{id\}) \ar[r] & \po Y,
} \]
where $\mathcal{E}$ is the set of marked maps of $Y$.
Now, assume that $U(f)$ is a relative $\Icell$ complex.
Then it is a transfinite composition $X_0 \to X_\lambda$, where for each $\alpha$, $X_\alpha \to X_{\alpha+1}$ is a pushout of a map $U_\alpha \to V_\alpha$ from $\I$.
We define a transfinite sequence $X = X'_0 \to \ldots \to X'_\lambda$ such that $U(X'_\alpha \to X'_\beta)$ equals to $X_\alpha \to X_\beta$ for every $\alpha$ and $\beta$.
Map $X'_\alpha \to X'_{\alpha+1}$ is defined as a pushout of $U^\flat_\alpha \to V^\flat_\alpha$.
Then $f$ factors as $X \to X'_\lambda \xrightarrow{g} Y$ so that $U(g)$ is an isomorphism.
Hence, $f$ is a relative $\Icell[\I^m]$ complex.
Finally, in the general case, $U(f)$ is a retract of a relative $\Icell$ complex $U(X) \to Z$.
Let $Z'$ be the marked object such that $U(Z') = Z$ and $K \to Z$ is marked if and only if it factors through $Y \to Z$.
Then $f$ is a retract of $X \to Z'$.
Hence, $f$ belongs to $\Icof[\I^m]$.
\end{proof}
Let $\mathcal{J}$ be a set of cofibrant marked objects.
We are going to define a model structure on $\C^m$ such that $\I^m$ is a set of generating cofibrations,
and for every $J \in \mathcal{J}$, map $U(J)^\flat \to J$ is a trivial cofibration.
Let us define a fibrant replacement functor $R^m$ for $\C^m$.
Let $R : \C \to \C$, $t_X : X \to R(X)$ be a fibrant replacement functor for $\C$.
For every marked $X$, underlying object of $R^m(X)$ is $R(U(X))$, and a map $K \to R(U(X))$ is marked if and only if it is homotopic to a map that
either factors as $K \to U(X) \xrightarrow{t_{U(X)}} R(U(X))$, where the first map is marked,
or factors through a marked map $K \to U(J)$ for some $J \in \mathcal{J}$.
We will say that a map $f$ of marked objects is a \emph{weak equivalence}
if and only if the underlying map of $f$ is a weak equivalence and $R^m(f)$ reflects marked maps.
\begin{prop}[2-out-of-3]
Weak equivalences of marked objects satisfy 2-out-of-3 property.
\end{prop}
\begin{proof}
Let $f : X \to Y$ and $g : Y \to Z$ be maps of marked objects such that $U(f)$ and $U(g)$ are equivalences.
If $R^m(f)$ and $R^m(g)$ reflect marked maps, then so is $R^m(g \circ f)$.
If $R^m(g \circ f)$ reflects marked maps, then so is $R^m(f)$.
Let us prove that if $R^m(g \circ f)$ reflects marked maps, then so is $R^m(g)$.
Let $k : K \to R(U(Y))$ be a map such that $R(U(g)) \circ k$ is marked.
Since $K$ is cofibrant and $R(U(f))$ is a weak equivalence between fibrant objects,
there exists a map $k' : K \to R(U(X))$ such that $R(U(f)) \circ k'$ is homotopic to $k$.
Since $R(U(g)) \circ k$ and $R(U(g \circ f)) \circ k'$ are homotopic and $R(U(g)) \circ k$ is marked, $R(U(g \circ f)) \circ k'$ is also marked.
Since $g \circ f$ reflects marked maps, $k'$ is marked.
Since $R(U(f)) \circ k'$ and $k$ are homotopic and $R(U(f)) \circ k'$ is marked, $k$ is also marked.
\end{proof}
The following lemma gives a useful explicit description of weak equivalences.
\begin{lem}[we]
If $f : X \to Y$ is a map of marked objects such that $U(f)$ is a weak equivalence,
then it is a weak equivalence if and only if for every $h : K \to R(U(X))$ and every marked $k : K \to U(Y)$,
if $R(U(f)) \circ h$ and $t_{U(Y)} \circ k$ are homotopic, then $h$ is marked in $R^m(X)$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
By the definition, $f$ is a weak equivalence if and only if for every $h : K \to R(U(X))$ such that $R(U(f)) \circ h$ is marked in $Y$, $h$ is marked in $R^m(X)$.
Map $R(U(f)) \circ h$ is marked in $R^m(Y)$ if and only if either there exists marked map $k : K \to U(Y)$ such that $t_{U(Y)} \circ k$ is homotopic to $R(U(f)) \circ h$,
or there exist $J \in \mathcal{J}$, a marked map $k : K \to U(J)$ and a map $g : U(J) \to R(U(Y))$ such that $g \circ k$ is homotopic to $R(U(f)) \circ h$.
We just need to prove that if the second case holds, then $h$ is marked in $R^m(X)$.
Since $U(J)$ is cofibrant and $R(U(f))$ is a weak equivalence between fibrant objects,
there exists a map $g' : U(J) \to R(U(X))$ such that $R(U(f)) \circ g'$ is homotopic to $g$.
Hence, $R(U(f)) \circ h$ is homotopic to $R(U(f)) \circ g' \circ k$.
Since $R(U(f))$ is a weak equivalence between fibrant objects, this implies that $h$ is homotopic to $g' \circ k$.
\end{proof}
\begin{prop}[iinj]
Every map $f : X \to Y \in \Iinj[\I^m]$ is a weak equivalence.
\end{prop}
\begin{proof}
Let $k : K \to U(Y)$ be a marked map, and let $h : K \to R(U(X))$ be a map such that $R(U(f)) \circ h$ and $t_{U(Y)} \circ k$ are homotopic.
Since $(K, G \{id\})$ is cofibrant, we have a lift in the following diagram:
\[ \xymatrix{ & X \ar[d]^f \\
(K, G \{id\}) \ar[r] \ar@{-->}[ur] & Y
} \]
Hence, there exists a marked map $k' : K \to U(X)$ such that $U(f) \circ k' = k$.
Note that $R(U(f)) \circ t_{U(X)} \circ k' = t_{U(Y)} \circ U(f) \circ k' = t_{U(Y)} \circ k \sim R(U(f)) \circ h$.
Since $R(U(f))$ is a weak equivalence between fibrant objects, this implies that $t_{U(X)} \circ k'$ is homotopic to $h$.
Hence, $h$ is marked in $R^m(X)$, and by the previous lemma, $f$ is a weak equivalence.
\end{proof}
The following lemma gives a useful characterization of trivial cofibrations.
\begin{lem}
Let $f : X \to Y$ be a cofibration of marked objects such that $U(f)$ is a weak equivalence.
Let $g : U(Y) \to R(U(X))$ be a map such that $g \circ U(f) = t_{U(X)}$.
Then $f$ is a weak equivalence if and only if for every marked $k : K \to U(Y)$, map $g \circ k$ is marked in $R^m(X)$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
First, suppose that $f$ is a weak equivalence.
Let $k : K \to U(Y)$ be a marked map.
Since $U(f)$ is a trivial cofibration, $R(U(f)) \circ g \circ k$ and $t_{U(Y)} \circ k$ are homotopic.
Hence, by \rlem{we}, map $g \circ k$ is marked.
Conversely, let $k : K \to U(Y)$ be a marked map, and let $h : K \to R(U(X))$ be a map such that $R(U(f)) \circ h$ is homotopic to $t_{U(Y)} \circ k$.
Note that $R(U(f)) \circ h \sim t_{U(Y)} \circ k \sim R(U(f)) \circ g \circ k$.
Since $R(U(f))$ is a weak equivalence between fibrant objects, this implies that $h$ is homotopic to $g \circ k$.
Since $g \circ k$ is marked, $h$ is also marked.
\end{proof}
Now, we need to establish the following simple lemma:
\begin{lem}
Let $f : X \to Y$ be a map of marked objects, and let $g : R(U(X)) \to R(U(Y))$ be a map such that the following diagram commutes:
\[ \xymatrix{ U(X) \ar[r]^{U(f)} \ar[d]_{t_{U(X)}} & U(Y) \ar[d]^{t_{U(Y)}} \\
R(U(X)) \ar[r]_g & R(U(Y))
} \]
Then $g$ preserves marked maps.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
Let $k : K \to R(U(X))$ be a marked map.
Then either there exists a marked map $k' : K \to U(X)$ such that $t_{U(X)} \circ k'$ is homotopic to $k$,
or there exist $J \in \mathcal{J}$, a marked map $k' : K \to U(J)$ and a map $h : U(J) \to R(U(X))$ such that $h \circ k'$ is homotopic to $k$.
If the first case holds, then $U(f) \circ k'$ is marked and $t_{U(Y)} \circ U(f) \circ k'$ is homotopic to $g \circ k$.
If the second case holds, then $g \circ h \circ k'$ is homotopic to $g \circ k$.
Thus $g \circ k$ is marked.
\end{proof}
\begin{prop}[pushouts-trans-comp]
Trivial cofibrations are closed under pushouts and transfinite compositions.
\end{prop}
\begin{proof}
First, let us prove the latter.
Let $c : X_0 \to X_\lambda$ be a transfinite composition of a sequence $X : \lambda \to \C^m$.
By \rprop{2-out-of-3}, weak equivalences are closed under composition.
Thus we may assume that $\lambda$ is a limit ordinal.
Let $k : K \to U(X_\lambda)$ be a marked map, and let $g : U(X_\lambda) \to R(U(X_0))$ be a map such that $g \circ c = t_{U(X_0)}$.
Since $k$ is marked, it factors through some marked map $k' : K \to U(X_\alpha)$.
Since $X_0 \to X_\alpha$ is a trivial cofibration, map $K \xrightarrow{k'} U(X_\alpha) \to U(X_\lambda) \xrightarrow{g} R(U(X_0))$ is marked.
Hence, $c$ is a trivial cofibration.
Now, let us prove that trivial cofibrations are closed under pushouts.
Consider the following pushout square, where $f$ is a trivial cofibration:
\[ \xymatrix{ X \ar[r]^p \ar[d]_f & Z \ar[d]^{f'} \\
Y \ar[r]_q & \po T
} \]
Let $k' : K \to U(T)$ be a marked map, and let $g' : U(T) \to R(U(Z))$ be a map such that $g' \circ U(f') = t_{U(Z)}$.
Then $k'$ factors through either $U(Z)$ or $U(Y)$.
If $k'$ factors through $U(Z)$, then this immediately implies that $g' \circ k'$ is marked.
If $k'$ factors through a marked map $k : K \to U(Y)$, then there exists a map $g : U(Y) \to R(U(X))$ such that $g \circ U(f) = t_{U(X)}$ and $g \circ k$ is marked.
By the previous lemma, $R(U(p)) \circ g \circ k$ is marked.
Since $f$ is a trivial cofibration, $R(U(p)) \circ g$ is homotopic to $g' \circ U(q)$.
Hence, $g' \circ U(q) \circ k = g' \circ k'$ is also marked.
\end{proof}
\section{Model structure on the category of marked objects}
\label{sec:model-structure}
To construct a model structure on $\C^m$, we will need the following theorem by Jeff Smith (see, for example, \cite[Proposition~A.2.6.8]{lurie-topos}):
\begin{thm}[mod-comb]
Let $\C$ be a locally presentable category, let $\I$ be a set of maps of $\C$, and let $\we$ be a class of maps of $\C$.
Suppose that the following conditions hold:
\begin{enumerate}
\item The intersection $\Icof \cap \we$ is closed under pushouts and transfinite compositions.
\item The full subcategory $\we$ of the category of arrows of $\C$ is accessible subcategory.
\item The class $\we$ has the 2-out-of-3 property.
\item $\Iinj \subseteq \we$.
\end{enumerate}
Then there exists a cofibrantly generated model structure on $\C$ with $\Icof$ as the class of cofibrations and $\we$ as the class of weak equivalences.
\end{thm}
We will also need the following theorem (see, for example, \cite[Theorem~2.1.19]{hovey}):
\begin{thm}[mod-cof]
Suppose that $\C$ is a complete and cocomplete category, $\we$ is a class of morphisms of $\C$, and $\I$, $\J$ are sets of morphisms of $\C$.
Then $\C$ is a cofibrantly generated model category with $\I$ as the set of generating cofibrations,
$\J$ as the set of generating trivial cofibrations, and $\we$ as the class of weak equivalences if and only if the following conditions are satisfied:
\begin{enumerate}
\item The domains of $\I$ and $\J$ are small relative to $\Icell$.
\item $\we$ has 2-out-of-3 property and is closed under retracts.
\item $\Iinj \subseteq \we$.
\item $\Jcell \subseteq \we \cap \Icof$.
\item Either $\Jinj \cap \we \subseteq \Iinj$ or $\Icof \cap \we \subseteq \Jcof$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{thm}
Now, we can prove our main result:
\begin{thm}[mark-main]
Let $\C$ be a model category, let $\mathcal{K}$ be a multiset of cofibrant objects of $\C$, and let $\mathcal{J}$ be a set of cofibrant marked objects.
Suppose that one of the following conditions hold:
\begin{enumerate}
\item \label{it:comb} $\C$ is a combinatorial model category.
\item \label{it:all-fib} Every object of $\C$ is fibrant and there exists a set $\I$ of generating cofibrations such that
the domains and the codomains of maps in $\I$ are small relative to $\Icell$.
\end{enumerate}
Then there exists a cofibrantly generated model structure on $\C^m$ in which a map is a cofibration if and only if the underlying map is a cofibration in $\C$.
Both adjoint pairs $(-)^\flat \dashv U$ and $U \dashv (-)^\sharp$ are Quillen pairs.
If $\C$ is left proper, then so is $\C^m$.
A marked object $X$ is fibrant in $\C^m$ if and only if the following conditions hold:
\begin{itemize}
\item The underlying object $U(X)$ is fibrant in $\C$
\item For every $J \in \mathcal{J}$, $X$ has RLP with respect to the map $U(J)^\flat \to J$.
\item Marked maps in $X$ are stable under homotopy (that is, if two maps $K \to U(X)$ are homotopic and one of them is marked, then so is the other).
\end{itemize}
\end{thm}
\begin{proof}
Every map in $\Iinj[\I^m]$ is a weak equivalence by \rprop{iinj},
trivial cofibrations are stable under pushouts and transfinite compositions by \rprop{pushouts-trans-comp},
weak equivalences has 2-out-of-3 property by \rprop{2-out-of-3},
and it is easy to see that they are closed under retracts.
First, assume that \eqref{it:comb} holds.
By \rprop{mark-comb}, $\C^m$ is locally presentable.
By \rthm{mod-comb}, we just need to prove that the class of weak equivalences is an accessible subcategory of $\C^m$.
Let $\J$ be a set of generating trivial cofibrations in $\C$.
Then we can take $R$ to be the functor obtained form the small object argument for $\J$.
Let $\J_\mathcal{K}$ be the set of maps $(C(K), G \{i_0\}) \to (C(K), G \{i_0,i_1\})$ for every $K \in \mathcal{K}$, where $[i_0,i_1] : K \amalg K \to C(K)$ is a cylinder object for $K$.
Let $\J_0$ be the set of maps $U(J)^\flat \to J$ for every $J \in \mathcal{J}$.
Then $R^m$ can be described as the composition of two functors $R_1$ and $R_2$.
The former is obtained from the small object argument for $\J^\flat$ and the latter from the small object argument for $\J_\mathcal{K} \cup \J_0$.
Thus $R^m$ preserves $\kappa$-filtered colimits for some regular cardinal $\kappa$.
Let $\C^m_0$ be the full subcategory of the arrow category of $\C^m$ on maps $f$ such that $U(f)$ is a weak equivalence and $f$ reflects marked maps.
Since $R^m$ preserves $\kappa$-filtered colimits, by \cite[Corollary~A.2.6.5]{lurie-topos},
to prove that the class of weak equivalences is an accessible subcategory of $\C^m$,
we just need to show that $\C^m_0$ is closed under $\kappa$-filtered colimits.
But this is obvious if we take $\kappa$ such that the class of weak equivalences in $\C$
is closed under $\kappa$-filtered colimits and every object in $\mathcal{K}$ is $\kappa$-presentable.
Now, assume that \eqref{it:all-fib} holds.
By \cite[Corollary~3.2]{f-model-structures}, there exists a set $\J_\I$ of generating trivial cofibrations for $\C$.
For every $J \in \mathcal{J}$ and marked $k : K \to U(J)$, let $Z_{J,k}$ be the following pushout:
\[ \xymatrix{ K \ar[r]^k \ar[d]_{i_0} & U(J) \ar[d] \\
C(K) \ar[r]_g & \po Z_{J,k}
} \]
Let $\J_1$ be the set of maps of the form $Z_{J,k}^\flat \to (Z_{J,k}, G\{ g \circ i_1 \})$ for every $J \in \mathcal{J}$ and marked $k : K \to U(J)$.
Then $\J^m = \J_\I^\flat \cup \J_\mathcal{K} \cup \J_0 \cup \J_1$ is a set of generating trivial cofibrations for $\C^m$.
Indeed, every map in $\J^m$ is cofibration and a weak equivalence.
Every map $f \in \J_\I^\flat$ is a weak equivalence since its underlying map is a weak equivalence and its codomain is flat.
Every map $f \in \J_\mathcal{K} \cup \J_1$ is a weak equivalence since $R^m(f)$ is an identity.
By \rthm{mod-cof}, we just need to prove that every weak equivalence that has RLP with respect to $\J^m$ also has RLP with respect to $\I^m$.
Let $f : X \to Y$ be such a map.
Since $U(f)$ is a weak equivalence and a fibration, it has RLP with respect to $\I$.
Hence, $f$ has RLP with respect to $\I^\flat$.
Since every object of $\C$ is fibrant, we can take $R$ to be the identity functor.
Let $k : K \to U(X)$ be a map such that $U(f) \circ k$ is marked.
Since $f$ is a weak equivalence, $k$ is marked in $R^m(X)$.
Thus either there exists a marked map $k' : K \to U(X)$ which is homotopic to $k$,
or there exist $J \in \mathcal{J}$, a marked map $k' : K \to U(J)$ and $h : U(J) \to U(X)$ such that $h \circ k'$ is homotopic to $k$.
If the first case holds, then $U(f) \circ k$ and $U(f) \circ k'$ are homotopic and are both marked.
Since $f$ has RLP with respect to $\J_\mathcal{K}$ and $k'$ is marked, $k$ is also marked.
If the second case holds, then there is a map $z : Z_{J,k'} \to U(X)$ such that $z \circ g \circ i_0 = k$.
Since $f$ has RLP with respect to $\J_1$ and $U(f) \circ k$ is marked, $k$ is also marked.
Thus $f$ has RLP with respect to $K^\flat \to (K, G \{id\})$ for every $K \in \mathcal{K}$.
This completes the construction of the model structure.
Now, let us consider the characterization of fibrant objects in this model category.
We need to prove that a marked object is fibrant if and only if it has RLP with respect to $\J^\flat \cup \J_\mathcal{K} \cup \J_0$,
where $\J$ is a set of generating trivial cofibrations for $\C$.
The ``only if'' direction follows from the fact that $\J^\flat \cup \J_\mathcal{K} \cup \J_0$ consists of trivial cofibrations.
Conversely, let $Z$ be a marked object that has RLP with respect to $\J^\flat \cup \J_\mathcal{K} \cup \J_0$.
Let $f : X \to Y$ be a trivial cofibration, and let $h : X \to Z$ be a map.
Since $U(Z)$ is fibrant, $U(h)$ factors through $t_{U(X)}$:
\[ \xymatrix{ U(X) \ar[r]^-{t_{U(X)}} \ar[d]_{U(f)} & R(U(X)) \ar[r]^h & U(Z) \\
U(Y) \ar@{-->}[ur]_g
} \]
Since $U(f)$ is a trivial cofibration, there exists a lift $g : U(Y) \to R(U(X))$ in the diagram above.
We just need to prove that $h \circ g$ preserves marked maps.
Let $k : K \to U(Y)$ be a marked map.
Since $f$ is a trivial cofibration, either there exists a marked map $k' : K \to U(X)$ such that $t_{U(X)} \circ k'$ is homotopic to $g \circ k$,
or there exist $J \in \mathcal{J}$, a marked map $k' : K \to U(J)$, and a map $j : U(J) \to R(U(X))$ such that $j \circ k'$ is homotopic to $g \circ k$.
If the first case holds, then $h \circ g \circ k$ is marked since marked maps in $Z$ are stable under homotopy.
If the second case holds, then $h \circ j \circ k'$ is marked since $Z$ has RLP with respect to $U(J)^\flat \to J$.
Hence, $h \circ g \circ k$ is also marked.
Thus $h \circ g$ preserves marked maps.
The fact that both adjoint pairs of functors $(-)^\flat \dashv U$ and $U \dashv (-)^\sharp$ are Quillen adjunctions
easily follows from the fact that both $(-)^\flat$ and $U$ preserve cofibrations and weak equivalences.
Finally, let us prove that if $\C$ is left proper, then so is $\C^m$.
Let $Z \to T$ be a pushout of a weak equivalence $f : X \to Y$ along a cofibration.
We may assume that $f$ is a trivial fibration.
Let $h : K \to R(U(Z))$ be a map, and let $k : K \to U(T)$ be a marked map.
Then $k$ factors through either $U(Z)$ or $U(Y)$.
In the first case, $K \to U(Z) \xrightarrow{t_{U(Z)}} R(U(Z))$ is homotopic to $h$.
Since the first map is marked, $h$ is also marked.
In the second case, we have a marked map $k' : K \to U(Y)$.
Since $f : X \to Y$ is a trivial fibration, $k'$ lifts to a marked map $K \to U(X)$.
Then $K \to U(X) \to U(Z) \to R(U(Z))$ is homotopic to $h$.
Since the first map is marked, $h$ is also marked.
Thus, in either case, $h$ is marked; hence $Z \to T$ is a weak equivalence.
\end{proof}
Since we often want to localize the model category of marked object, it is useful to have a simple description of homotopy function complexes.
Let $X$ and $Y$ be a pair of marked objects such that $X$ is cofibrant and $Y$ is fibrant.
Let $QU(X)^\bullet$ be a cosimplicial frame on $U(X)$.
Then vertices of the Kan complex $\Map(U(X),U(Y)) = \Hom(QU(X)^\bullet,U(Y))$ can be identified with maps $U(X) \to U(Y)$.
We will denote this bijection by $e : \Hom(\Delta^0,\Map(U(X),U(Y))) \simeq \Hom(U(X),U(Y))$.
Let $x$ and $y$ be a pair of vertices of $\Map(U(X),U(Y))$ that belongs to the same component.
If $e(x) : U(X) \to U(Y)$ lifts to a map of marked objects, then so does the map $e(y)$.
Indeed, there exists an edge $\Delta^1 \to \Map(U(X),U(Y))$ between $x$ and $y$.
But such an edge corresponds to a homotopy between $e(x)$ and $e(y)$.
Since $Y$ is fibrant and $e(x)$ preserves marked maps, so does every map homotopic to $e(x)$.
Let $\Map(X,Y)$ be the Kan subcomplex of $\Map(U(X),U(Y))$ which consists of those components of
$\Map(U(X),U(Y))$ in which some (and hence every) vertex corresponds to a map $U(X) \to U(Y)$ that lifts to a map of marked objects.
\begin{lem}[mark-map]
Kan complex $\Map(X,Y)$ is equivalent to the homotopy function complex from $X$ to $Y$.
\end{lem}
\begin{proof}
We may assume that $QU(X)^\bullet$ is a fibrant cosimplicial frame on $U(X)$.
Then we can define a fibrant cosimplicial frame $QX^\bullet$ on $X$ as $(QU(X)^\bullet,\mathcal{E})$,
where $\mathcal{E}$ consists of those maps $K \to QU(X)^\bullet$ such that $K \to QU(X)^\bullet \to U(X)$ is marked.
Map $L_n QX^\bullet \to QX^n$ is a cofibration since its underlying map $L_n QU(X)^\bullet \to QU(X)^n$ is a cofibration.
Map $QX^n \to X$ has RLP with respect to $\I^\flat$ since $QU(X)^\bullet$ is fibrant.
It also has RLP with respect to $K^\flat \to (K, G \{id\})$ by definition of $QX^n$.
Thus it is a trivial fibration.
Kan complex $\Hom(QX^\bullet,Y)$ is a subcomplex of $\Map(X,Y)$.
Let us prove that they are actually equal.
Consider a simplex $\Delta^n \to \Map(X,Y)$.
Such simplex corresponds to a map $QU(X)^n \to U(Y)$.
We need to show that this map lifts to a map $QX^n \to Y$.
Let $k : K \to QU(X)^n$ be a marked map.
Then it is homotopic to $K \xrightarrow{k} QU(X)^n \to U(X) \simeq QU(X)^0 \to QU(X)^n$,
where the last map is given by any map $\Delta^0 \to \Delta^n$.
By definition of $\Map(X,Y)$ every such map gives a marked map in $Y$.
Since $Y$ is fibrant, $K \xrightarrow{k} QU(X)^n \to U(Y)$ is also marked.
\end{proof}
\section{Marked simplicial sets}
\label{sec:marked-simp-sets}
In this section for every set $\mathcal{L}$ of simplicial sets, we define a model category $\sSet_\mathcal{L}$ of marked simplicial sets
which represents the $(\infty,1)$-category of $(\infty,1)$-categories which have a limit for every diagram of every shape from $\mathcal{L}$.
In particular, if $\mathcal{L} = \{ \varnothing, \Lambda^2_2 \}$, then $\sSet_\mathcal{L}$ represents the $(\infty,1)$-category of finitely complete $(\infty,1)$-categories.
For every set of simplicial sets $\mathcal{L}$, we define set $\mathcal{K}$ as $\{ \Delta^0 \join L\ |\ L \in \mathcal{L} \}$.
Let $\sSet_\mathcal{L}$ be the category of \K-marked objects.
Let $\J$ be the following set of maps of $\sSet_\mathcal{L}$:
\begin{enumerate}
\item For every $L \in \mathcal{L}$, maps $L^\flat \to (\Delta^0 \join L, \{ id : \Delta^0 \join L \to \Delta^0 \join L \})$.
\item For every $n > 0$ and $L \in \mathcal{L}$, maps $(\partial \Delta^n \join L, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \join L : \Delta^0 \join L \to \partial \Delta^n \join L \}) \to (\Delta^n \join L, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \join L : \Delta^0 \join L \to \Delta^n \join L \})$.
\end{enumerate}
We define a model structure on $\sSet_\mathcal{L}$ as the left Bousfield localization of the model structure
defined in section~\ref{sec:model-structure} (with $\mathcal{J} = \varnothing$) with respect to $\J$.
The following propositions give us a characterization of fibrant objects and fibrations between them in $\sSet_\mathcal{L}$.
\begin{prop}[mark-fib-obj]
For every marked simplicial set $Z$, the following conditions are equivalent:
\begin{enumerate}
\item \label{it:fib} $Z$ is a fibrant object of $\sSet_\mathcal{L}$.
\item \label{it:exp} $Z$ is a quasi-category which has a limit for every diagram of every shape from $\mathcal{L}$ and a cone is marked in $Z$ if and only if it is a limit cone.
\end{enumerate}
\end{prop}
\begin{proof}
It is easy to see that \eqref{it:fib} implies \eqref{it:exp}.
To prove the converse, we need to define homotopy function complexes for $\sSet_\mathcal{L}$.
First, recall that the inclusion of Kan complexes into quasi-categories has a right adjoint which we denote by $E$ (see, for example, \cite[Proposition~1.2.5.3]{lurie-topos}).
Let $\Fun(X,Y)$ be the internal Hom in the category of simplicial sets.
By \cite[Corollary~3.1.4.4]{lurie-topos}, $E(\Fun(X,Y))$ is a homotopy function complex in the Joyal model structure.
If $X$ and $Y$ are marked simplicial sets, then by \rlem{mark-map}, we can define a homotopy function complex $\Map(X,Y)$ as certain subcomplex of $E(\Fun(U(X),U(Y)))$.
Let $X$ be a marked simplicial set of the form $(A \join L, \{ p \join L \})$ for some $L \in \mathcal{L}$ and $p : \Delta^0 \to A$.
Then we can give an equivalent definition of a homotopy function complex $\Map'(X,Y)$ in terms of fat join.
Let $\Map'(X,Y)$ be the subcomplex of $E(\Fun(A \fjoin L, Y))$ which consists of those components in which some (and hence every) vertex
corresponds to a map $f : A \fjoin L \to Y$ such that $\Delta^0 \fjoin L \xrightarrow{p \fjoin L} A \fjoin L \xrightarrow{f} Y$ is a limit cone.
Since $A \fjoin L \to A \join L$ is a weak equivalence in the Joyal model structure, induced map $\Map(X,Y) \to \Map'(X,Y)$ is a weak equivalence of Kan complexes.
An object $Z$ of $\sSet_\mathcal{L}$ is fibrant if and only if it is a quasi-category, marked maps in $Z$ are stable under homotopy,
and for every map $X \to Y$ in $\J$, induced map of Kan complexes $\Map(Y,Z) \to \Map(X,Z)$ is a weak equivalence.
Let $Z$ be a marked simplicial set that satisfies \eqref{it:exp}.
Since limits cones are stable under homotopy, we just need to prove that $\Map(Y,Z) \to \Map(X,Z)$ is a weak equivalence for every $X \to Y$ in $\J$.
Thus we only need to prove that for every $p : X \to Z$, the fiber of $\Map(Y,Z) \to \Map(X,Z)$ over $p$ is contractible.
First, let us consider maps of the form $L^\flat \to (\Delta^0 \join L, \{ id \})$.
Since $L^\flat$ is flat, $\Map(L^\flat,Z) = E(\Fun(L,U(Z)))$.
For any simplicial sets $K$, $A$ and $Z'$ and every map $p : K \to Z'$, we have the following Cartesian square:
\[ \xymatrix{ \Fun(A,Z'^{/p}) \ar[r] \ar[d] \pb & \Fun(A \fjoin K, Z') \ar[d] \\
\Delta^0 \ar[r]_-p & \Fun(K,Z')
} \]
In particular, if we let $K = L$, $A = \Delta^0$ and $Z' = U(Z)$, then we obtain the following Cartesian square:
\[ \xymatrix{ U(Z)^{/p} \ar[r] \ar[d] \pb & \Fun(\Delta^0 \fjoin L, U(Z)) \ar[d] \\
\Delta^0 \ar[r]_-p & \Fun(L,U(Z))
} \]
Since $E$ is a right adjoint, it preserves pullbacks.
Hence, fiber of $\Map'((\Delta^0 \join L, \{ id \}), Z) \to \Map(L^\flat, Z)$ is the subcomplex of $E(U(Z)^{/p})$
spanned by vertices that correspond to limit cones, and it is easy to see that it is contractible (see, for example, \cite[Lemma~2.11]{szumilo}).
Now, let us consider maps of the form $(\partial \Delta^n \join L, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \join L \}) \to (\Delta^n \join L, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \join L \})$.
First, let us consider the special case when $L = \varnothing$.
We prove that fibers of $\Map((\Delta^n, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \}), Z) \to \Map((\partial \Delta^n, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \}), Z)$ are contractible by induction on $n$.
If $n = 1$, then for every $p : \Delta^0 \to X$, we have the following diagram:
\[ \xymatrix{ U(Z)^{/p} \ar[d] \ar[r] \pb & \Fun(\Delta^1, U(Z)) \ar[d] \\
U(Z) \ar[d] \ar[r] \pb & \Fun(\partial \Delta^1, U(Z)) \ar[d] \\
\Delta^0 \ar[r]_p & U(Z)
} \]
If $p$ is final, then $U(Z)^{/p} \to U(Z)$ is a weak equivalence (see, for example, \cite[Corollary~1.2.12.5]{lurie-topos}).
Since every map $\Delta^0 \to \Map((\partial \Delta^1, \{ \Delta^{\{1\}} \}), Z)$ factors through $U(Z)$ for some final $p$,
fibers of $\Map((\Delta^1, \{ \Delta^{\{1\}} \}), Z) \to \Map((\partial \Delta^1, \{ \Delta^{\{1\}} \}), Z)$ are contractible.
Now, assume $n > 1$.
Consider the following diagram:
\[ \xymatrix{ \Map((\Delta^n, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \}), Z) \ar[d] \\
\Map((\partial \Delta^n, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \}), Z) \ar[r] \ar[d] \pb & \Map((\Delta^{n-1}, \{ \Delta^{\{n-1\}} \}), Z) \ar[d] \\
\Map((\Lambda^n_1, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \}), Z) \ar[r] & \Map((\partial \Delta^{n-1}, \{ \Delta^{\{n-1\}} \}), Z)
} \]
Since $\Lambda^n_1 \to \Delta^n$ is a weak equivalence in the Joyal model structure, map
\[ \Map((\Delta^n, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \}), Z) \to \Map((\Lambda^n_1, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \}), Z) \]
is also a weak equivalence.
By induction hypothesis, map
\[ \Map((\Delta^{n-1}, \{ \Delta^{\{n-1\}} \}), Z) \to \Map((\partial \Delta^{n-1}, \{ \Delta^{\{n-1\}} \}), Z) \]
is a weak equivalence.
Since it is a fibration, map
\[ \Map((\partial \Delta^n, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \}), Z) \to \Map((\Lambda^n_1, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \}), Z) \]
is also a weak equivalence.
Hence, by 2-out-of-3 property, $\Map((\Delta^n, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \}), Z) \to \Map((\partial \Delta^n, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \}), Z)$ is a weak equivalence.
Finally, we consider the general case.
For every $p : L \to U(Z)$, we have the following diagram:
\[ \xymatrix{ \Fun(\Delta^n, U(Z)^{/p}) \ar[r] \ar[d] \pb & \Fun(\Delta^n \fjoin L, U(Z)) \ar[d] \\
\Fun(\partial \Delta^n, U(Z)^{/p}) \ar[r] \ar[d] \pb & \Fun(\partial \Delta^n \fjoin L, U(Z)) \ar[d] \\
\Delta^0 \ar[r]_-p & \Fun(L,U(Z))
} \]
It follows that the following square is Cartesian:
\[ \xymatrix{ \Map(\Delta^n, U(Z)^{/p}) \ar[r] \ar[d] \pb & \Map'(\Delta^n \join L, U(Z)) \ar[d] \\
\Map(\partial \Delta^n, U(Z)^{/p}) \ar[r] & \Map'(\partial \Delta^n \join L, U(Z))
} \]
Since every vertex $\Delta^0 \to \Map'(\partial \Delta^n \join L, U(Z))$ factors through $\Map(\partial \Delta^n, U(Z)^{/p})$
for some $p$, it is enough to show that every fiber of \[ \Map(\Delta^n, U(Z)^{/p}) \to \Map(\partial \Delta^n, U(Z)^{/p}) \] is contractible.
But this follows from the special case when $L = \varnothing$.
\end{proof}
\begin{prop}[mark-fib-map]
A map $f : X \to Y$ between fibrant marked simplicial sets is a fibration if and only if its underlying map is a fibration in the Joyal model structure.
\end{prop}
\begin{proof}
\Rprop{mark-fib-obj} implies that an object of $\sSet_\mathcal{L}$ is fibrant if and only if it is a quasi-category
and has RLP with respect to sets $\J$ and $\J_\mathcal{K}$ (which was defined in \rthm{mark-main}).
By \cite[Proposition~3.6]{f-model-structures}, a map of marked simplicial sets with fibrant codomain is a fibration
if and only if it is a fibration in the Joyal model structure and has RLP with respect to $\J \cup \J_\mathcal{K}$.
Let us prove that every map $f : X \to Y$ between fibrant marked simplicial sets which is a fibration in the Joyal model structure has RLP with respect to $\J \cup \J_\mathcal{K}$.
Since $X$ has RLP with respect to $\J_\mathcal{K}$, $f$ also has RLP with respect to this set.
Consider the following commutative square:
\[ \xymatrix{ L \ar[r] \ar[d] & U(X) \ar[d]^f \\
\Delta^0 \join L \ar[r]_v \ar@{-->}[ur]^g & U(Y),
} \]
where $v$ is marked in $Y$.
Since $X$ is fibrant, there exists a marked map $g : \Delta^0 \join L \to U(X)$ such that the top triangle in the square above commutes.
Since $f \circ g$ and $v$ are limit cones, they are homotopic relative to $L$.
Since $U(f)$ is a fibration in the Joyal model structure, we can lift this homotopy to obtain a lift in the square above such that both triangles commute.
The same argument shows that $f$ has RLP with respect to maps $(\partial \Delta^n \join L, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \join L \}) \to (\Delta^n \join L, \{ \Delta^{\{n\}} \join L \})$.
\end{proof}
Let $\kappa$ be a regular cardinal, and let $\mathcal{L}$ be the set of all (representatives of) sets with cardinality less than $\kappa$ together with simplicial set $\Lambda^2_2$.
Let $\sSet_\mathcal{L}^f$ be the full subcategory of $\sSet_\mathcal{L}^f$ on the fibrant object.
Then $\sSet_\mathcal{L}^f$ is a category with fibrations.
Let $\qcat^c$ be the category of $\kappa$-complete quasi-categories and functors that preserve $\kappa$-small limits.
A structure of a category with fibrations on $\qcat^c$ was constructed in \cite{szumilo}.
These two categories with fibrations are isomorphic.
Indeed, \rprop{mark-fib-obj} implies that forgetful functor $U : \sSet_\mathcal{L}^f \to \qcat^c$ is an isomorphism of categories.
Thus we just need to show that $U$ preserves weak equivalences and fibrations.
Weak equivalences in both cases are just weak equivalences of underlying quasi-categories.
Fibrations in $\qcat^c$ are fibrations of underlying quasi-categories.
By \rprop{mark-fib-map}, this is also true in $\sSet_\mathcal{L}^f$.
\bibliographystyle{amsplain}
\bibliography{ref}
\end{document}