-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 1
/
ch1_4.tex
652 lines (623 loc) · 19.8 KB
/
ch1_4.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
\section{Limits and Continuity.}\label{sec 1.4}
Consider the function $f$ defined by
\[
f(x) = \frac{x^{2} - 3x + 2}{x - 2},
\prov{x \neq 2}.
\]
The domain of $f$ is the set of all real numbers
with the exception of the number $2$,
which has been excluded because substitution of $x = 2$
in the expression for $f(x)$
yields the undefined term $\frac{0}{0}$.
On the other hand,
$x^{2} - 3x + 2 = (x - 1)(x - 2)$
and
\begin{equation}
\frac{(x - 1)(x - 2)}{x - 2} = x - 1,
\provx{provided $x \neq 2$}.
\label{eq1.4.1}
\end{equation}
The proviso is essential.
Without it, (1) is false because,
if $x = 2$,
the left side is undefined
and the right side is equal to 1.
We therefore obtain
\[
f(x) = x - 1,
\prov{x \neq 2}.
\]
The graph of the function $x - 1$ is a straight line $L$;
so the graph of $f$ is the punctured line
obtained from $L$
by omitting the one point $(2,1)$
(see Figure \figref{1.22}).
\putfig{2truein}{scanfig1_22}{}{fig 1.22}
Although the function $f$ is not defined at $x = 2$,
we know its behavior for values of $x$ near $2$.
The graph makes it clear that if $x$ is close to $2$,
then $f(x)$ is close to $1$.
In fact, the values $f(x)$ can be brought arbitrarily close to $1$
by taking $x$ sufficiently close to $2$.
We express this fact by writing
\[
\lim_{x \goesto 2} {\frac{x^2 - 3x + 2}{x -2}} = 1,
\]
which is translated:
\emph{The limit of $\frac{x^2 - 3x +2}{x - 2}$
is $1$ as $x$ approaches $2$.}
\begin{example}\label{exam 1.4.1}
Evaluate
$\lim_{x \goesto 3} {\frac{\sqrt{x} - \sqrt{3}}{x - 3}}$.
The function
$\frac{\sqrt{x} - \sqrt{3}}{x - 3}$
is not defined at $x = 3$.
The following algebraic manipulation
puts the function in a form
in which its behavior close to $3$ can be read off easily:
\begin{eqnarray*}
\frac{\sqrt{x} - \sqrt{3}}{x - 3}
&=& \frac{\sqrt{x} - \sqrt{3}}{x - 3}
\frac{\sqrt{x} + \sqrt{3}}{\sqrt{x} + \sqrt{3}} \\
&=& \frac{x - 3}{x - 3} \frac{1}{\sqrt{x} + \sqrt{3}} \\
&=& \frac{1}{\sqrt{x} + \sqrt{3}}, \provx{if $x \neq 3$}.
\end{eqnarray*}
Again note the proviso $x \neq 3$:
When $x = 3$,
the last quantity in the preceding equations
is equal to $\frac{1}{\sqrt{3} + \sqrt{3}}$,
but the first quantity is not defined.
However, by taking values of $x$ close to 3,
it is clear that the corresponding values of
$\frac{1}{\sqrt{x} + \sqrt{3}}$
can be brought as close as we please to
$\frac{1}{2 \sqrt{3}}$.
We conclude that
\[
\lim_{x \goesto 3}
{\frac {\sqrt{x} - \sqrt{3}}{x - 3}}
=
\frac{1}{2{\sqrt{3}}}.
\]
In words:
The limit of
$\frac {\sqrt{x} - \sqrt{3}}{x - 3}$,
as $x$ approaches $3$,
is $\frac{1}{2{\sqrt{3}}}$.
\end{example}
\begin{example}\label{exam 1.4.2}
If $f(x) = \frac{1}{x}$,
evaluate
$\lim_{x \goesto 0} f(x)$.
The function $f$ is not defined at $0$
(i.e., the number 0 is not in the domain of $f$).
From the graph of $f$ and the list of ordered pairs $(x, f(x))$
shown in Figure \figref{1.23},
\putfig{3truein}{scanfig1_23}{}{fig 1.23}
it is clear that there are values of $x$
arbitrarily close to 0 for which the
corresponding values of $f(x)$
are arbitrarily large in absolute value
(see Table \tabref{1.5}).
We conclude that
$\lim_{x \goesto 0}{\frac{1}{x}}$ does not exist.
\begin{table}\label{table 1.5}
\centering
\begin{tabular}{r|l} \hline
$x$ & $f(x) = \frac{1}{x}$ \vspace {1ex}\\ \hline
1 & 1 \\
0.1 & 10 \\
0.01 & 100 \\
0.001 & 1000 \\
0.0001 & 10000 \\
$\cdots$ & $\cdots$ \\
-1 & -1 \\
-0.1 & -10 \\
-0.01 & -100 \\
-0.001 & -1000 \\
-0.0001 & -10000 \\
$\cdots$ & $\cdots$ \\ \hline
\end{tabular}
\caption{}
\end{table}
\end{example}
Thus far our examples have been confined to
the problem of finding the limit of a function
at a number which happens to lie outside
the domain of the function.
If it happens that the number $a$
is in the domain of $f$,
then it is frequently possible to determine
$\lim_{x \goesto a}f(x)$ at a glance.
Consider, for example,
the function
$f(x) = 2x^2 - x - 2$.
As $x$ takes on values closer and closer to 3,
the corresponding value of
$2x^{2}$ approaches $18$,
the value of $-x$ approaches $-3$,
and the constant $-2$ does not change.
We conclude that
\[
\lim_{x \goesto 3} {(2x^2 - x - 2)} = 13,
\]
or that, for this particular function, $\lim_{x \goesto 3}f(x) = f(3)$.
\begin{example}\label{exam 1.4.3}
It would be incorrect to suppose that
if $a$ is in the domain of $f$,
then it always happens that
$\lim_{x \goesto a}f(x) = f(a)$.
Consider the two functions $f$ and $g$ defined by
\[
f(x) =
\dilemma
{x^2+1 & \mbox{if $|x| > 0$}}
{2 & \mbox{if $x = 0$}}
\]
\[
g(x) =
\dilemma
{x^2 + 1 & \mbox{if $x \geq 0$},}
{-x^2 -1 & \mbox{if $x < 0$}.}
\]
Both these functions are defined on the whole real line;
i.e., domain $f$ = domain $g = \R$
(see Figure \figref{1.24}).
\putfig{4.5truein}{scanfig1_24}{}{fig 1.24}
Furthermore,
\[
f(0) = 2
\intext{and}
g(0) = 1.
\]
As $x$ approaches 0, however,
it is clear that $x^2 + 1$ approaches 1 and not 2.
Hence
\[
\lim_{x \goesto 0}f(x) = 1 \neq f(0).
\]
[Note that in computing $\lim_{x \goesto a}f(x)$,
we consider values of $f(x)$
for all $x$ arbitrarily close to $a$
\emph{but not equal to} $a$.
This point will be made explicit
when we give the formal definition.]
Turning to $g$,
we see that the value of $g(x)$ near 0
depends on whether $x$ is positive or negative.
For any small positive number $x$,
the corresponding number $g(x)$ is close to 1,
but if $x$ is small in absolute value and negative,
then $g(x)$ is close to $-1$.
Since there is no reason to prefer numbers of one sign to those of the other,
we conclude that there is no limit.
Thus
\[
\lim_{x \goesto 0} g(x) \; \mbox{ does not exist}.
\]
\end{example}
The reader may feel that Example \exampref{1.4.3}
loses force because the functions used to make the point
were in some sense artificial.
There is some truth in the objection.
Recall, however,
that one of our major objectives
is to reduce the class of all functions
to those we wish to study in this course.
After defining
$\lim_{x \goesto a}f(x)$ precisely,
we shall turn our point of view around
and use this definition as the major tool
in the problem of deciding what does constitute a well-behaved function.
The conceptual problems
in trying to give an exact meaning
to the expression
$\lim_{x \goesto a}f(x) = b$
revolve around phrases such as
``arbitrarily close,"
``sufficiently near,"
and ``arbitrarily small."
After all,
there is no such thing in any absolute sense
as a \emph{small} positive real number.
The number $0.000001$
is small in most contexts,
but in comparison with $0.000000000001$
it is huge.
However, we can assert that one number is
\emph{smaller than} another.
Moreover,
the actual closeness of one number $x$
to another number $a$
is just the distance between them:
It is $|x - a|$.
One way to say that a function $f$ takes on values
arbitrarily close to a number $b$
is to state that,
for any positive real number $\epsilon$,
there are numbers $x$ such that $|f(x) - b| < \epsilon$.
We are stating that
no matter what positive number $\epsilon$ is selected,
$10^{17}$, or $10^{-17}$, or $10^{-127}$,
there are numbers $x$ so that the distance between $f(x)$ and $b$
is smaller than $\epsilon$.
Thus the difficulty inherent in the phrase ``arbitrarily close"
has been circumvented by the prefix ``for any."
To finish the definition,
we want to be able to say that
$f(x)$ is arbitrarily close to $b$
whenever $x$ is sufficiently close,
but not equal, to $a$.
What does ``sufficiently close" mean?
The answer is this:
If an arbitrary $\epsilon > 0$ is chosen
with which to measure the distance between $f(x)$ and $b$,
then it must be the case that
there is a number $\delta > 0$
such that whenever $x$ is in the domain of $f$
and within a distance $\delta$ of $a$,
but not equal to $a$,
then the distance between $f(x)$ and $b$
is less than $\epsilon$.
The situation is pictured in Figure \figref{1.25}.
\putfig{2truein}{scanfig1_25}{}{fig 1.25}
First $\epsilon > 0$ is chosen arbitrarily.
There must then exist a number $\delta > 0$
such that whenever
$x$ lies in the interval $(a - \delta, a + \delta)$,
and $x \neq a$ then
the point $(x, f(x))$ lies in the shaded rectangle.
We summarize by giving the definition:
Let $f$ be a real-valued function of a real variable.
Then \dt{the limit as $x$ approaches $a$ of $f(x)$ is $b$},
written
\[
\lim_{x \goesto a} {f(x)} = b,
\]
if, for any $\epsilon > 0$,
there exists $\delta > 0$
such that whenever $x$ is in the domain of $f$
and $0 < |x - a| < \delta$,
then $|f(x) - b| < \epsilon$.
(There is a strong tradition for using
the Greek letters $\epsilon$ and $\delta$
in the definition of limit.
In fact, the part of calculus
that deals with rigorous proofs of the various properties of limits
is sometimes referred to as ``epsilonics.")
\begin{example}\label{exam 1.4.4}
The idea behind a formal definition
can sometimes be grasped most easily
by looking at an example
where the condition is not satisfied.
Consider the function $g$
defined in Example \exampref{1.4.3}
whose graph is drawn in Figure \figref{1.24}(b).
We shall prove that
$\lim_{x \goesto 0} {g(x)} \neq 1$.
To do this,
we must establish the negation of the limit condition:
There is an $\epsilon > 0$
such that,
for any $\delta > 0$,
there is a number $x$ in the domain of $g$ such that
$0 < |x| < \delta$ and $|g(x) - 1| \geq \epsilon$.
There are many possible choices for $\epsilon$.
To be specific,
take $\epsilon = \frac{1}{2}$.
We must now show that for every positive number $\delta$,
there is a nonzero number $x$ in the open interval
$(-\delta, \delta)$
such that the distance between $g(x)$ and $1$
is greater than or equal to $\frac{1}{2}$
(Figure \figref{1.26}).
\putfig{3truein}{scanfig1_26}{}{fig 1.26}
Take $x = -\frac{\delta}{2}$.
This number is non-zero,
lies in $(-\delta, \delta)$,
and furthermore
\[
g(x) = g \Bigl( -\frac{\delta}{2} \Bigr) = -\frac{\delta^2}{4} - 1 < -1 .
\]
Hence $|g(x) - 1| > 2 \geq \frac{1}{2}$.
\end{example}
The basic limit theorem is the following:
\begin{prop}\label{thm 1.4.1}\label{thm blt}
If $\lim_{x \goesto a} f(x) = b_1$ and $\lim_{x \goesto a} g(x) = b_2$, then
\begin{quote}
{\rm (i)}
$\lim_{x \goesto a} [ f(x) + g(x) ] = b_1 + b_2.$
{\rm (ii)}
$\lim_{x \goesto a} cf(x) = cb_1.$
{\rm (iii)}
$\lim_{x \goesto a} f(x)g(x) = b_1b_2.$
{\rm (iv)}
$\lim_{x \goesto a} \frac{f(x)}{g(x)} = \frac{b_1}{b_2}
\provx{provided $b_2 \neq 0$}$.
\end{quote}
\end{prop}
The proofs are given in Appendix A.
They are not difficult,
and (i) and (ii) especially follow directly from
the definition of limit and the properties of the absolute value.
Some ingenuity in algebraic manipulation is required for (iii) and (iv).
Note that we have already assumed that this theorem is true.
For example,
the assertion that $\lim_{x \goesto 3} (2x^2 - x - 2) = 13$
is a corollary of (i), (ii), and (iii).
If a function $f$ is defined for every $x$ in $\R$
and if its graph contains no breaks,
then it is apparent from looking at the graph that
$\lim_{x \goesto a}f(x) = f(a)$.
Logically, however, this intuitive point of view is backward.
So far, we have constructed the graph of a function $f$
by plotting a few isolated points
and then joining them with a smooth curve.
In so doing we are assuming that if
$x$ is close to $a$,
then $f(x)$ is close to $f(a)$.
That is, we are assuming that
$\lim_{x \goesto a} {f(x)} = f(a)$.
Now that we have given a formal definition of limit,
we shall reverse ourselves
and use it to say precisely what is meant by
a function whose graph has no breaks.
Sueh a function is ealled continuous.
The definitions are as follows:
A real-valued function $f$ of a real variable is
\dt{continuous at $a$}
if $a$ is in the domain of $f$
and $\lim_{x \goesto a}f(x) = f(a)$.
The function $f$ is simply said to be \dt{continuous}
if it is continuous at every number in its domain.
A continuous function whose domain is an interval
is one whose graph has no breaks,
but the graph need not be a smooth curve.
For example, the function with the sawtooth graph
shown in Figure \figref{1.27} is continuous.
\putfig{3.5truein}{scanfig1_27}{}{fig 1.27}
Many functions that are not continuous
fail to be so at only a few isolated places.
Thus the function $f$ in Example \exampref{1.4.3},
whose graph is drawn in Figure \figref{1.24}(a),
has its only discontinuity at 0.
It is continuous everywhere else.
Finally, we emphasize the fact that
there are two conditions in the definition of continuity.
Even though
$\lim_{x \goesto 1} {\frac{x^{3} - 1}{x - 1}} = 3$,
the function
$\frac{x^{3} - 1}{x - 1}$
is not continuous at $x = 1$
simply because it is not defined there.
If two functions $f$ and $g$ are continuous at $a$,
then it is not difficult to prove that
the sum $f + g$ is also continuous at $a$.
To begin with,
$a$ is in the domain of $f + g$
since we have $(f + g)(a) = f(a) + g(a)$.
Furthermore, we know that
$\lim_{x \goesto a}f(x) = f(a)$
and that
$\lim_{x \goesto a} g(x) = g(a)$.
It follows by Theorem \thref{blt}(i)
that
\[
\lim_{x \goesto a} {[f(x) + g(x)]} = f(a) + g(a).
\]
Since $f(x) + g(x) = (f + g)(x)$, we get
\[
\lim_{x \goesto a} {(f + g)(x)} = (f + g)(a),
\]
which proves the continuity of $f + g$ at $a$.
The other parts of the basic limit theorem \thref{blt}
imply similar results about the products and quotients
of continuous functions.
We summarize these in
\begin{prop}\label{thm 1.4.2}\label{thm bct}
If two functions $f$ and $g$ are continuous at $a$, then so are
\begin{quote}
(i) $f + g$.
(ii) $c f, \provx{for any constant $c$}$.
(iii) $f g$.
(iv) $\frac{f}{g}, \provx{provided $g(a) \neq 0$}$.
\end{quote}
\end{prop}
A real-valued function $f$ of one real variable
is called a \dt{polynomial}
if there exist a nonnegative integer $n$ and real numbers
$a_{0}, a_{1}, \ldots, a_{n}$
such that, for every real number $x$,
\[
f(x) = a_{0} + a_{1}x + ... + a_{n}x^{n} .
\]
The following functions are all examples of polynomials:
\begin{eqnarray*}
f(x) &=& 2 - 4x + 3x^2, \\
f(y) &=& 117y^{239} + {\frac{3}{2}}y + \pi, \\
f(x) &=& x, \\
f(x) &=& 5, \\
g(s) &=& (s^2 + 2)(s^5 - 1) = s^7 + 2s^5 - s^2 - 2 .
\end{eqnarray*}
It is equally important to be able to recognize that a given function is not a polynomial. Examples of functions which are not polynomials are
\begin{eqnarray*}
f(x) &=& |x|, \\
f(x) &=& \frac{1}{x}, \\
f(x) &=& x^2 + x + 3x^{-2}, \\
f(x) &=& \sqrt{x}, \\
F(y) &=& (y^2 - 1)^{3/2} .
\end{eqnarray*}
Algebraically the set of all polynomials is much like the set of integers:
The sum, difference, and product of any two polynomials
is again a polynomial,
but, in general,
the quotient of two polynomials is not a polynomial.
Moreover, the algebraic axioms
\ref{axiom.i} through \ref{axiom.v}
listed in Section \secref{1.1}
also hold.
Just as a rational number is one
which can be expressed as the ratio of two integers,
a \dt{rational function}
is one which can be expressed as the ratio of two polynomials.
Examples are the functions
\begin{eqnarray*}
f(x) &=& \frac{x^3 + 2x + 2}{x^4 + 1}, \\
g(x) &=& x^{-3} = \frac{1}{x^3}, \\
f(x) &=& x^2 + 2x + 1 = \frac{x^2 + 2x + 1}{1}, \\
g(x) &=& \pi.
\end{eqnarray*}
The domain of every polynomial
is the entire set $\R$ of real numbers.
Similarly, the domain of a given rational function
$\frac{p(x)}{q(x)}$,
where $p(x)$ and $q(x)$ are polynomials,
is the whole set $\R$
with the exception of those numbers $x$
for which $q(x) = 0$.
Furthermore, we have
\begin{prop}\label{thm 1.4.3}
Every polynomial is a continuous function, and every rational function
$\frac{p(x)}{q(x)}$ is continuous except at those values of $x$
for which $q(x) = 0$.
\end{prop}
\begin{proof}
The identity function $x$
is clearly continuous,
and so is every constant function.
Since every polynomial can be constructed from
the identity function $x$
and from constants
using only the sums and products of these and the resulting functions,
it follows from Theorem \thref{1.4.2}
that every polynomial is continuous.
The assertion about the continuity of rational functions then
follows from part (iv) of Theorem \thref{1.4.2}.
\end{proof}
It is occasionally useful
to modify the definition of
$\lim_{x \goesto a}f(x)$
to allow $x$ to approach $a$ from only one side:
\begin{picture}(400,60)(0,0)
\put(85,35){\vector(-1,0){20}}
\put(205,35){\vector(1,0){20}}
\put(60,20){\line(0,1){8}}
\put(100,20){\line(0,1){8}}
\put(190,20){\line(0,1){8}}
\put(230,20){\line(0,1){8}}
\put(0,20){either}
\put(30,20){\line(30,0){100}}
\put(140,20){or}
\put(160,20){\line(30,0){100}}
\put(60,5){a}
\put(100,5){x}
\put(190,5){x}
\put(230,5){a}
\end{picture}
When this is done, we speak of either the limit from the right
or the limit from the left and write either
\[
\lim_{x \goesto a+}f(x) \;\;\; \mbox{or}\;\;\; \lim_{x \goesto a-}f(x),
\]
according as the additional condition is $x > a$ or $x < a$.
Thus for the function
\[
f(x) = \left\{ \begin{array}{ll}
x - 1, & x \geq 2, \\
x^{2} - 1, & x < 2 ,
\end{array}
\right.
\]
whose graph is shown in Figure \figref{1.28},
\putfig{4.5truein}{scanfig1_28}{}{fig 1.28}
the limit of $f(x)$ as $x$ approaches 2 does not exist.
Nevertheless, we obtain
\[
\lim_{x \goesto 2+} {f(x)} = 1,\;\;\; \lim_{x \goesto 2-} {f(x)} = 3.
\]
Similarly, for the function $g$ in Figure \figref{1.24}(b),
we have
$\lim_{x \goesto 0+}g(x) = 1$, $\lim_{x \goesto 0-}g(x) = -1$.
The graph of the rational function
\[
f(x) = \frac{x + 1}{x} = 1 + \frac{1}{x}, \;\;\; x \neq 0,
\]
together with a list of some of the ordered pairs $(x,f(x))$
that comprise $f$ is shown in Figure \figref{1.29}.
\putfig{3truein}{scanfig1_29}{}{fig 1.29}
From both Figure \figref{1.29} and Table \tabref{1.6}
it is clear that as $x$ increases without bound,
$f(x)$ becomes arbitrarily close to 1.
We express this fact by writing
\[
\lim_{x \goesto +\infty} {\frac{x + 1}{x}} = 1.
\]
\begin{table}\label{table 1.6}
\centering
\begin{tabular}{r|l} \hline
$x$ & $f(x)$ \vspace {1ex} \\ \hline
1 & 2 \\
10 & 1.1 \\
100 & 1.01 \\
1,000 & 1.001 \\
1,000,000 & 1.000001 \\
$\vdots $ & \\ \hline
\end{tabular}
\caption{}
\end{table}
Since $f(x)$ also becomes arbitrarily close to 1
as $x$ decreases without bound,
i.e., as $-x$ increases without bound,
we write
\[
\lim_{x \goesto {-\infty}} {\frac{x + 1}{x}} = 1.
\]
The definition is as follows:
Let $f$ be a real-valued function of a real variable.
Then \dt{the limit of $f(x)$ is $b$ as $x$ increases without bound},
written
\[
\lim_{x \goesto {+\infty}} {f(x)} = b,
\]
if, for any $\epsilon > 0$,
there exists $\delta > 0$ such that
whenever $x$ is in the domain of $f$
and $\delta < x$,
then $|f(x) - b| < \epsilon$.
The analogous definition for
$\lim_{x \goesto -\infty}f(x) = b$ is obvious.
The symbols $+\infty$ and $-\infty$
can also be used to refer to
the behavior of the values of the function
as well as the independent variable.
If, as $x$ approaches $a$,
the corresponding value $f(x)$ of the function increases without bound,
we may express the fact by writing
\[
\lim_{x \goesto \infty} f(x) = + \infty.
\]
The reader should be able to attach the correct meanings
to the various other possibilities:
\begin{eqnarray*}
\lim_{x \goesto a} f(x) &=& - \infty, \\
\lim_{x \goesto -\infty} f(x) &=& + \infty, \\
\lim_{x \goesto a+} f(x) &=& - \infty, \; \mbox{etc.}
\end{eqnarray*}
It is essential to keep in mind that
\emph{$+\infty$ and $-\infty$ are not numbers}.
They are not elements of $\R$.
They are used simply as convenient abbreviations
for describing the unbounded characteristics of certain functions.
The symbol $+\infty$ (or simply $\infty$)
in an expression for a bound
will always mean that the quantity referred to increases without limit
in the positive direction.
Similarly, $-\infty$ always indicates the negative direction.
Thus we shall not say
$\lim_{x \goesto 0}\frac{1}{x} = \infty$.
But we do say
\begin{eqnarray*}
\lim_{x \goesto 0+} \frac{1}{x} &=& \infty, \\
\lim_{x \goesto 0-} \frac{1}{x} &=& -\infty, \\
\lim_{x \goesto 0} \Big|\frac{1}{x} \Big| &=& \infty.
\end{eqnarray*}