-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
formal.tex
1244 lines (1103 loc) · 49.1 KB
/
formal.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
% !TeX root = hott-online.tex
\titleformat{\chapter}[display]{\fontsize{23}{25}\fontseries{m}\fontshape{it}\selectfont}{\chaptertitlename}{20pt}{\fontsize{35}{35}\fontseries{b}\fontshape{n}\selectfont}
\chapter{Formal type theory}
\label{cha:rules}
\index{formal!type theory|(}%
\index{type theory!formal|(}%
\index{rules of type theory|(}%
Just as one can develop mathematics in set theory without explicitly using the axioms of Zermelo--Fraenkel set theory,
in this book we have developed mathematics in univalent foundations without explicitly referring to a formal
system of homotopy type theory. Nevertheless, it is important to \emph{have} a
precise description of homotopy type theory as a formal system in order to, for example,
%
\begin{itemize}
\item state and prove its metatheoretic properties, including logical
consistency,
\item construct models, e.g.\ in simplicial sets, model categories, higher toposes,
etc., and
\item implement it in proof assistants like \Coq or \Agda.
\index{proof!assistant}
\end{itemize}
%
Even the logical consistency\index{consistency} of homotopy type theory, namely that in the empty context there is no term $a:\emptyt$, is not obvious: if we had erroneously
chosen a definition of equivalence for which $\eqv{\emptyt}{\unit}$, then
univalence would imply that $\emptyt$ has an element, since $\unit$ does.
Nor is it obvious that, for example, our definition of $\Sn^1$ as a higher
inductive type yields a type which behaves like the ordinary circle.
There are two aspects of type theory which we must pin down before addressing
such questions. Recall from the Introduction that type theory
comprises a set of rules specifying when the judgments $a:A$ and $a\jdeq a':A$
hold---for example, products are characterized by the rule that whenever $a:A$
and $b:B$, $(a,b):A\times B$. To make this precise, we must first define
precisely the syntax of terms---the objects $a,a',A,\dots$ which these judgments
relate; then, we must define precisely the judgments and their rules of
inference---the manner in which judgments can be derived from other judgments.
In this appendix, we present two formulations of Martin-L\"{o}f type
theory, and of the extensions that constitute homotopy type theory.
The first presentation (\cref{sec:syntax-informally}) describes the syntax of
terms and the forms of judgments as an extension of the untyped
$\lambda$-calculus, while leaving the rules of inference informal.
The second (\cref{sec:syntax-more-formally}) defines the terms, judgments,
and rules of inference inductively in the style of natural deduction, as
is customary in much type-theoretic literature.
\section*{Preliminaries}
\label{sec:formal-prelim}
In \cref{cha:typetheory}, we presented the two basic \define{judgments}
\index{judgment}
of type theory. The first, $a:A$, asserts that a term $a$ has type $A$. The second,
$a\jdeq b:A$, states that the two terms $a$ and $b$ are \define{judgmentally
equal}
\index{equality!judgmental}
\index{judgmental equality}
at type $A$. These judgments are inductively defined by a set of
inference rules described in \cref{sec:syntax-more-formally}.
To construct an element $a$ of a type $A$ is to derive $a:A$; in the book, we
give informal arguments which describe the construction of $a$, but formally,
one must specify a precise term $a$ and a full derivation that $a:A$.
However, the main difference between the presentation of type theory in the book
and in this appendix is that here judgments are explicitly
formulated in an ambient \define{context},
\index{context}
or list of assumptions, of the form
\[
x_1:A_1, x_2:A_2,\dots,x_n:A_n.
\]
An element $x_i : A_i$ of the context expresses the assumption that the
variable
\index{variable}%
$x_i$ has type $A_i$. The variables $x_1, \ldots, x_n$ appearing in
the context must be distinct. We abbreviate contexts with the letters $\Gamma$
and $\Delta$.
The judgment $a:A$ in context $\Gamma$ is written
\[ \oftp\Gamma aA \]
and means that $a:A$ under the assumptions listed in $\Gamma$. When the list of
assumptions is empty, we write simply
\[ \oftp{}aA \]
or
\[ \oftp\emptyctx aA \]
where $\emptyctx$ denotes the empty context. The same applies to the equality
judgment
\[
\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{b}{A}
\]
However, such judgments are sensible only for \define{well-formed} contexts,
\index{context!well-formed}%
a notion captured by our third and final judgment
\[
\wfctx{(x_1:A_1, x_2:A_2,\dots,x_n:A_n)}
\]
expressing that each $A_i$ is a type in the context $x_1:A_1,
x_2:A_2,\dots,x_{i-1}:A_{i-1}$. In particular, therefore, if $\oftp\Gamma aA$ and
$\wfctx\Gamma$, then we know that each $A_i$ contains only the variables
$x_1,\dots,x_{i-1}$, and that $a$ and $A$ contain only the variables
$x_1,\dots,x_n$.
\index{variable!in context}
In informal mathematical presentations, the context is
implicit. At each point in a proof, the mathematician knows which
variables are available and what types they have, either by historical
convention ($n$ is usually a number, $f$ is a function, etc.) or
because variables are explicitly introduced with sentences such as
``let $x$ be a real number''. We discuss some benefits of using explicit
contexts in \cref{sec:more-formal-pi,sec:more-formal-sigma}.
We write $B[a/x]$ for the \define{substitution}
\index{substitution}%
of a term $a$ for free occurrences of
the variable~$x$ in the term $B$, with possible capture-avoiding
renaming of bound variables,
\index{variable!and substitution}%
as discussed in
\cref{sec:function-types}. The general form of substitution
%
\[
B[a_1,\dots,a_n/x_1,\dots,x_n]
\]
%
substitutes expressions $a_1,\dots,a_n$ for the variables
$x_1,\dots,x_n$ simultaneously.
To \define{bind a variable $x$ in an expression $B$}
\indexdef{variable!bound}%
means to incorporate both of them into a larger expression, called an \define{abstraction},
\indexdef{abstraction}%
whose purpose is to express the fact that $x$ is ``local'' to $B$, i.e., it
is not to be confused with other occurrences of $x$ appearing
elsewhere. Bound variables are familiar to programmers, but less so to mathematicians.
Various notations are used for binding, such as $x \mapsto B$,
$\lam x B$, and $x \,.\, B$, depending on the situation. We may write $C[a]$ for the
substitution of a term $a$ for the variable in the abstracted expression, i.e.,
we may define $(x.B)[a]$ to be $B[a/x]$. As discussed in
\cref{sec:function-types}, changing the name of a bound variable everywhere within an expression (``$\alpha$-conversion'')
\index{alpha-conversion@$\alpha $-conversion}%
does not change the expression. Thus, to be very
precise, an expression is an equivalence class of syntactic forms
which differ in names of bound variables.
One may also regard each variable $x_i$ of a judgment
\[
x_1:A_1, x_2:A_2,\dots,x_n:A_n \vdash a : A
\]
to be bound in its \define{scope},
\indexdef{variable!scope of}%
\index{scope}%
consisting of the expressions $A_{i+1},
\ldots, A_n$, $a$, and $A$.
\section{The first presentation}
\label{sec:syntax-informally}
The objects and types of our type theory may be written as terms using
the following syntax, which is an extension of $\lambda$-calculus with
\emph{variables} $x, x',\dots$,
\index{variable}%
\emph{primitive constants}
\index{primitive!constant}%
\index{constant!primitive}%
$c,c',\dots$, \emph{defined constants}\index{constant!defined} $f,f',\dots$, and term forming
operations
%
\[
t \production x \mid \lam{x} t \mid t(t') \mid c \mid f
\]
%
The notation used here means that a term $t$ is either a variable $x$, or it
has the form $\lam{x} t$ where $x$ is a variable and $t$ is a term, or it has
the form $t(t')$ where $t$ and $t'$ are terms, or it is a primitive constant
$c$, or it is a defined constant $f$. The syntactic markers '$\lambda$', '(',
')', and '.' are punctuation for guiding the human eye.
We use $t(t_1,\dots,t_n)$ as an abbreviation for the repeated application
$t(t_1)(t_2)\dots (t_n)$. We may also use \emph{infix}\index{infix notation} notation, writing $t_1\;
\star\; t_2$ for $\star(t_1,t_2)$ when $\star$ is a primitive or defined
constant.
Each defined constant has zero, one or more \define{defining equations}.
\index{equation, defining}%
\index{defining equation}%
There are two kinds of defined constant. An \emph{explicit}
\index{constant!explicit}
defined constant $f$ has a single defining equation
\[ f(x_1,\dots,x_n)\defeq t,\]
where $t$ does not involve $f$.
%
For example, we might introduce the explicit defined constant $\circ$ with defining equation
\[ \circ (x,y)(z) \defeq x(y(z)),\]
and use infix notation $x\circ y$ for $\circ(x,y)$. This of course is just composition of functions.
The second kind of defined constant is used to specify a (parameterized) mapping
$f(x_1,\dots,x_n,x)$, where $x$ ranges over a type whose elements are generated
by zero or more primitive constants. For each such primitive constant $c$ there
is a defining equation of the form
\[
f(x_1,\dots,x_n,c(y_1,\dots,y_m)) \defeq t,
\]
where $f$ may occur in $t$, but only in such a way that it is clear that the
equations determine a totally defined function. The paradigm examples of such
defined functions are the functions defined by primitive recursion on the
natural numbers. We may call this kind of definition of a function a \emph{total
recursive definition}.
\index{total!recursive definition}%
In computer science and logic this kind of definition
of a function on a recursive data type has been called a \define{definition by
structural recursion}.
\index{definition!by structural recursion}%
\index{structural!recursion}%
\index{recursion!structural}%
\define{Convertibility}
\index{convertibility of terms}%
\index{term!convertibility of}%
$t \conv t'$ between terms $t$
and $t'$ is the equivalence relation generated by the defining equations for constants,
the computation rule\index{computation rule!for function types}
%
\[
(\lam{x} t)(u) \defeq t[u/x],
\]
%
and the rules which make it a \emph{congruence} with respect to application and $\lambda$-abstraction\index{lambda abstraction@$\lambda$-abstraction}:
%
\begin{itemize}
\item if $t \conv t'$ and $s \conv s'$ then $t(s) \conv t'(s')$, and
\item if $t \conv t'$ then $(\lam{x} t) \conv (\lam{x} t')$.
\end{itemize}
\noindent
The equality judgment $t \jdeq u : A$ is then derived by the following single rule:
%
\begin{itemize}
\item if $t:A$, $u:A$, and $t \conv u$, then $t \jdeq u : A$.
\end{itemize}
%
Judgmental equality is an equivalence relation.
\subsection{Type universes}
We postulate a hierarchy of \define{universes} denoted by primitive constants
\index{type!universe}
%
\begin{equation*}
\UU_0, \quad \UU_1, \quad \UU_2, \quad \ldots
\end{equation*}
%
The first two rules for universes say that they form a cumulative hierarchy of types:
%
\begin{itemize}
\item $\UU_m : \UU_n$ for $m < n$,
\item if $A:\UU_m$ and $m \le n$, then $A:\UU_n$,
\end{itemize}
%
and the third expresses the idea that an object of a universe can serve as a type and stand to the
right of a colon in judgments:
%
\begin{itemize}
\item if $\Gamma \vdash A : \UU_n$, and $x$ is a new variable,%
\footnote{By ``new'' we mean that it does not appear in $\Gamma$ or $A$.}
then $\vdash (\Gamma, x:A)\; \ctx$.
\end{itemize}
%
In the body of the book, an equality judgment $A \jdeq B : \UU_n$ between types
$A$ and $B$ is usually abbreviated to $A \jdeq B$. This is an instance of
typical ambiguity\index{typical ambiguity}, as we can always switch to a larger universe, which however does not affect the validity of the judgment.
The following conversion rule allows us to replace a type by one equal to it in a typing judgment:
%
\begin{itemize}
\item if $a:A$ and $A \jdeq B$ then $a:B$.
\end{itemize}
\subsection{Dependent function types (\texorpdfstring{$\Pi$}{Π}-types)}
We introduce a primitive constant $c_\Pi$, but write
$c_\Pi(A,\lam{x} B)$ as $\tprd{x:A}B$. Judgments concerning
such expressions and expressions of the form $\lam{x} b$ are introduced by the following rules:
%
\begin{itemize}
\item if $\Gamma \vdash A:\UU_n$ and $\Gamma,x:A \vdash B:\UU_n$, then $\Gamma \vdash \tprd{x:A}B : \UU_n$
\item if $\Gamma, x:A \vdash b:B$ then $\Gamma \vdash (\lam{x} b) : (\tprd{x:A} B)$
\item if $\Gamma\vdash g:\tprd{x:A} B$ and $\Gamma\vdash t:A$ then $\Gamma\vdash g(t):B[t/x]$
\end{itemize}
%
If $x$ does not occur freely in $B$, we abbreviate $\tprd{x:A} B$ as the non-dependent function type
$A\rightarrow B$ and derive the following rule:
%
\begin{itemize}
\item if $\Gamma\vdash g:A \rightarrow B$ and $\Gamma\vdash t:A$ then $\Gamma\vdash g(t):B$
\end{itemize}
Using non-dependent function types and leaving implicit the context $\Gamma$, the rules above can be written in the following alternative style that we use in the rest of this section of the appendix.
%
\begin{itemize}
\item if $A:\UU_n$ and $B:A\to\UU_n$, then $\tprd{x:A}B(x) : \UU_n$
\item if $x:A \vdash b:B$ then $ \lam{x} b : \tprd{x:A} B(x)$
\item if $g:\tprd{x:A} B(x)$ and $t:A$ then $g(t):B(t)$
\end{itemize}
%
\subsection{Dependent pair types (\texorpdfstring{$\Sigma$}{Σ}-types)}
We introduce primitive constants $c_\Sigma$ and $c_{\mathsf{pair}}$. An
expression of the form $c_\Sigma(A,\lam{a} B)$ is written as $\sm{a:A}B$,
and an expression of the form $c_{\mathsf{pair}}(a,b)$ is written as $\tup
a b$. We write $A\times B$ instead of $\sm{x:A} B$ if $x$ is not free in $B$.
Judgments concerning such expressions are introduced by the following
rules:
%
\begin{itemize}
\item if $A:\UU_n$ and $B: A \rightarrow \UU_n$, then $\sm{x:A}B(x) : \UU_n$
\item if, in addition, $a:A$ and $b:B(a)$, then $\tup a b:\sm{x:A}B(x)$
\end{itemize}
%
If we have $A$ and $B$ as above, $C : \sm{x:A}B(x) \rightarrow \UU_m$, and
\[
d:\tprd{x:A}{y:B(x)} C(\tup x y)
\]
we can introduce a defined constant
\[
f:\tprd{p:\sm{x:A}B(x)} C(p)
\]
with the defining equation
\[
f(\tup x y)\defeq d(x,y).
\]
%
Note that $C$, $d$, $x$, and $y$ may contain extra implicit parameters $x_1,\ldots,x_n$ if they were obtained in some non-empty context; therefore, the fully explicit recursion schema is
%
\begin{narrowmultline*}
f(x_1,\dots,x_n,\tup{x(x_1,\dots,x_n)}{y(x_1,\dots,x_n)}) \defeq
\narrowbreak
d(x_1,\dots,x_n,\tup{x(x_1,\dots,x_n)}{y(x_1,\dots,x_n)}).
\end{narrowmultline*}
\subsection{Coproduct types}
We introduce primitive constants $c_+$, $c_\inlsym$, and $c_\inrsym$.
We write $A+B$ instead of $c_+(A,B)$, $\inl(a)$ instead of
$c_\inlsym(a)$, and $\inr(a)$ instead of $c_\inrsym(a)$:
%
\begin{itemize}
\item if $A,B : \UU_n$ then $A + B : \UU_n$
\item moreover, $\inl: A \rightarrow A+B$ and $\inr: B \rightarrow A+B$
\end{itemize}
%
If we have $A$ and $B$ as above, $C : A+B \rightarrow \UU_m$,
$d:\tprd{x:A} C(\inl(x))$, and $e:\tprd{y:B} C(\inr(y))$,
then we can introduce a defined constant $f:\tprd{z:A+B}C(z)$ with the defining equations
%
\begin{equation*}
f(\inl(x)) \defeq d(x)
\qquad\text{and}\qquad
f(\inr(y)) \defeq e(y).
\end{equation*}
\subsection{The finite types}
We introduce primitive constants $\ttt$, $\emptyt$, $\unit$, satisfying the following rules:
%
\begin{itemize}
\item $\emptyt : \UU_0$, $\unit : \UU_0$
\item $\ttt:\unit$
\end{itemize}
Given $C : \emptyt \rightarrow \UU_n$ we can introduce a defined constant $f:\tprd{x:\emptyt} C(x)$, with no defining equations.
Given $C : \unit \rightarrow \UU_n$ and $d : C(\ttt)$ we can introduce a defined constant $f:\tprd{x:\unit} C(x)$, with defining equation $f(\ttt) \defeq d$.
\subsection{Natural numbers}
The type of natural numbers is obtained by introducing primitive constants
$\N$, $0$, and $\suc$ with the following rules:
%
\begin{itemize}
\item $\N : \UU_0$,
\item $0:\N$,
\item $\suc:\N\rightarrow \N$.
\end{itemize}
%
Furthermore, we can define functions by primitive recursion. If we have
$C : \N \rightarrow \UU_k $ we can introduce a defined constant $f:\tprd{x:\N}C(x)$ whenever we have
%
\begin{align*}
d & : C(0) \\
e & : \tprd{x:\N}(C(x)\rightarrow C(\suc (x)))
\end{align*}
%
with the defining equations
%
\begin{equation*}
f(0) \defeq d
\qquad\text{and}\qquad
f(\suc (x)) \defeq e(x,f(x)).
\end{equation*}
\subsection{\texorpdfstring{$W$}{W}-types}
For $W$-types we introduce primitive constants $c_\wtypesym$ and $c_\suppsym$.
An expression of the form $c_\wtypesym(A,\lam{x} B)$ is written as
$\wtype{x:A}B$, and an expression of the form $c_\suppsym(x,u)$ is written
as $\supp(x,u)$:
%
\begin{itemize}
\item if $A:\UU_n$ and $B: A \rightarrow \UU_n$, then $\wtype{x:A}B(x) : \UU_n$
\item if moreover, $a:A$ and $g:B(a)\rightarrow \wtype{x:A}B(x)$ then $\supp(a,g):\wtype{x:A}B(x)$.
\end{itemize}
%
Here also we can define functions by total recursion. If we have $A$ and $B$
as above and $C : \wtype{x:A}B(x) \rightarrow \UU_m$, then we can introduce a defined constant
$f:\tprd{z:\wtype{x:A}B(x)} C(z)$ whenever we have
\[
d:\tprd{x:A}{u:B(x) \rightarrow \wtype{x:A}B(x)}((\tprd{y:B(x)}C(u(y))) \rightarrow C(\supp(x,u)))
\]
with the defining equation
\[
f(\supp(x,u)) \defeq d(x,u,f\circ u).
\]
\subsection{Identity types}
We introduce primitive constants $c_\idsym$ and $c_{\refl{}}$. We write
$\id[A] a b$ for $c_\idsym(A,a,b)$ and $\refl a$ for $c_{\refl{}}(A,a)$, when
$a:A$ is understood:
%
\begin{itemize}
\item If $A : \UU_n$, $a:A$, and $b:A$ then $\id[A] a b : \UU_n$.
\item If $a:A$ then $\refl a :\id[A] a a $.
\end{itemize}
%
Given $a:A$, if $y:A, z:\id[A] a y \vdash C : \UU_m$ and
$\vdash d:C[a,\refl{a}/y,z]$ then we can introduce a defined constant
\[
f:\tprd{y:A}{z:\id[A] a y} C
\]
with defining equation
\[
f(a,\refl{a})\defeq d.
\]
\section{The second presentation}
\label{sec:syntax-more-formally}
In this section, there are three kinds of judgments
\begin{mathpar}
\wfctx\Gamma
\and
\oftp\Gamma{a}{A}
\and
\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{a'}{A}
\end{mathpar}
which we specify by providing inference rules for deriving them. A typical \define{inference rule}
\indexsee{inference rule}{rule}%
\indexdef{rule}%
has the form
%
\begin{equation*}
\inferrule*[right=\textsc{Name}]
{\mathcal{J}_1 \\ \cdots \\ \mathcal{J}_k}
{\mathcal{J}}
\end{equation*}
%
It says that we may derive the \define{conclusion} $\mathcal{J}$, provided that we have
already derived the \define{hypotheses} $\mathcal{J}_1, \ldots, \mathcal{J}_k$.
(Note that, being judgments rather than types, these are not hypotheses \emph{internal} to the type theory in the sense of \cref{sec:types-vs-sets}; they are instead hypotheses in the deductive system, i.e.\ the metatheory.)
On the
right we write the \textsc{Name} of the rule, and there may be extra side conditions that
need to be checked before the rule is applicable.
A \define{derivation}
\index{derivation}%
of a judgment is a tree constructed from such inference
rules, with the judgment at the root of the tree. For example, with the rules given below, the following is a derivation of
$\oftp{\emptyctx}{\lamu{x:\unit} x}{\unit\to\unit}$.
%
\begin{mathpar}
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\intro]
{\inferrule*[right=$\Vble$]
{\inferrule*[right=\ctx-\textsc{ext}]
{\inferrule*[right=$\unit$-\form]
{\inferrule*[right=\ctx-\textsc{emp}]
{\ }
{\wfctx {\emptyctx}}}
{\oftp{}{\unit}{\UU_0}}}
{\wfctx {\tmtp x\unit}}}
{\oftp{\tmtp x\unit}{x}{\unit}}}
{\oftp{\emptyctx}{\lamu{x:\unit} x}{\unit\to\unit}}
\end{mathpar}
\subsection{Contexts}
\label{subsec:contexts}
\index{context}%
A context is a list
%
\begin{equation*}
\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \tmtp{x_2}{A_2}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_n}{A_n}
\end{equation*}
%
which indicates that the distinct variables
\index{variable}%
$x_1, \ldots, x_n$ are assumed to have types $A_1, \ldots, A_n$, respectively. The list may be empty. We abbreviate contexts with the letters $\Gamma$ and $\Delta$, and we may juxtapose them to form larger contexts.
The judgment $\wfctx{\Gamma}$ formally expresses the fact that $\Gamma$ is a well-formed context, and is governed by the rules of inference
%
\begin{mathpar}
\inferrule*[right=\ctx-\textsc{emp}]
{\ }
{\wfctx\emptyctx}
\and
\inferrule*[right=\ctx-\textsc{ext}]
{\oftp{\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_{n-1}}{A_{n-1}}}{A_n}{\UU_i}}
{\wfctx{(\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_n}{A_n})}}
\end{mathpar}
%
with a side condition for the second rule: the variable $x_n$ must be distinct from the variables $x_1, \ldots, x_{n-1}$.
Note that the hypothesis and conclusion of $\ctx$-\textsc{ext} are judgments of different forms: the hypothesis says that in the context of variables $x_1, \ldots, x_{n-1}$, the expression $A_n$ has type $\UU_i$; while the conclusion says that the extended context $(\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_n}{A_n})$ is well-formed.
(It is a meta-theoretic property of the system that if $\oftp{\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_{n}}{A_{n}}}{b}{B}$ is derivable, then the context $(\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_{n}}{A_{n}})$ must be well-formed; thus $\ctx$-\textsc{ext} does not need to hypothesize well-formedness of the context to the left of $x_n$.)
\subsection{Structural rules}
\index{structural!rules|(}%
\index{rule!structural|(}%
The fact that the context holds assumptions is expressed by the rule which says that we may derive those typing judgments which are listed in the context:
%
\begin{mathpar}
\inferrule*[right=$\Vble$]
{\wfctx {(\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_n}{A_n})} }
{\oftp{\tmtp{x_1}{A_1}, \ldots, \tmtp{x_n}{A_n}}{x_i}{A_i}}
\end{mathpar}
%
As with $\ctx$-\textsc{ext}, the hypothesis and conclusion of the rule $\Vble$ are judgments of different forms, only now they are reversed: we start with a well-formed context and derive a typing judgment.
The following important principles, called \define{substitution}
\indexdef{rule!of substitution}%
and
\define{weakening},
\indexdef{rule!of weakening}%
need not be explicitly assumed. Rather, it is possible to
show, by induction on the structure of all possible derivations, that whenever
the hypotheses of these rules are derivable, their conclusion is also
derivable.\footnote{Such rules are called \define{admissible}\indexdef{rule!admissible}\indexsee{admissible!rule}{rule, admissible}.}
For the typing judgments these principles are manifested as
%
\begin{mathpar}
\inferrule*[right=$\Subst_1$]
{\oftp\Gamma{a}{A} \\ \oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA,\Delta}{b}{B}}
{\oftp{\Gamma,\Delta[a/x]}{b[a/x]}{B[a/x]}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\Weak_1$]
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ \oftp{\Gamma,\Delta}{b}{B}}
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA,\Delta}{b}{B}}
\end{mathpar}
and for judgmental equalities they become
\begin{mathpar}
\inferrule*[right=$\Subst_2$]
{\oftp\Gamma{a}{A} \\ \jdeqtp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA,\Delta}{b}{c}{B}}
{\jdeqtp{\Gamma,\Delta[a/x]}{b[a/x]}{c[a/x]}{B[a/x]}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\Weak_2$]
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ \jdeqtp{\Gamma,\Delta}{b}{c}{B}}
{\jdeqtp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA,\Delta}{b}{c}{B}}
\end{mathpar}
%
In addition to the judgmental equality rules given for each type former, we also
assume that judgmental equality is an equivalence relation respected by typing.
\begin{mathparpagebreakable}
\inferrule*{\oftp\Gamma{a}{A}}{\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{a}{A}}
\and
\inferrule*{\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{b}{A}}{\jdeqtp\Gamma{b}{a}{A}}
\and
\inferrule*{\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{b}{A} \\ \jdeqtp\Gamma{b}{c}{A}}{\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{c}{A}}
\and
\inferrule*{\oftp\Gamma{a}{A} \\ \jdeqtp\Gamma{A}{B}{\UU_i}}{\oftp\Gamma{a}{B}}
\and
\inferrule*{\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{b}{A} \\ \jdeqtp\Gamma{A}{B}{\UU_i}}{\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{b}{B}}
\end{mathparpagebreakable}
%
Additionally, for all the type formers below, we assume rules stating that each constructor preserves definitional equality in each of its arguments; for instance, along with the $\Pi$-\intro\ rule, we assume the rule
\[
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\intro-eq]
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{A}{A'}{\UU_i} \\
\jdeqtp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{B}{B'}{\UU_i} \\
\jdeqtp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{b}{b'}{B}}
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\lamu{x:A} b}{\lamu{x:A'} b'}{\tprd{x:A} B}}
\]
However, we omit these rules for brevity.
\index{rule!structural|)}%
\index{structural!rules|)}%
\subsection{Type universes}
\index{type!universe}%
We postulate an infinite hierarchy of type universes
%
\begin{equation*}
\UU_0, \quad \UU_1, \quad \UU_2, \quad \ldots
\end{equation*}
%
Each universe is contained in the next, and any type in $\UU_i$ is also in $\UU_{i+1}$:
%
\begin{mathpar}
\inferrule*[right=\UU-\textsc{intro}]
{\wfctx \Gamma }
{\oftp\Gamma{\UU_i}{\UU_{i+1}}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=\UU-\textsc{cumul}]
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i}}
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_{i+1}}}
\end{mathpar}
%
We shall set up the rules of type theory in such a way that $\oftp\Gamma{a}{A}$
implies $\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i}$ for some $i$. In other words, if $A$ plays the role of a type then it is in some universe. Another property of our type system is that $\jdeqtp\Gamma{a}{b}{A}$
implies $\oftp\Gamma{a}{A}$ and $\oftp\Gamma{b}{A}$.
\subsection{Dependent function types (\texorpdfstring{$\Pi$}{Π}-types)}
\label{sec:more-formal-pi}
\index{type!dependent function}%
\index{type!function}%
In \cref{sec:function-types}, we introduced non-dependent functions $A\to B$ in
order to define a family of types as a function $\lam{x:A} B:A\to\UU_i$, which
then gives rise to a type of dependent functions $\tprd{x:A} B$. But with explicit contexts
we may replace $\lam{x:A} B:A\to\UU_i$ with the judgment
%
\begin{equation*}
\oftp{\tmtp xA}{B}{\UU_i}.
\end{equation*}
%
Consequently, we may define dependent functions directly, without reference to non-dependent ones. This way we follow the general principle that each type former, with its constants and rules, should be introduced independently of all other type formers.
%
In fact, henceforth each type former is introduced systematically by:
\begin{itemize}
\item a \define{formation rule}, stating when the type former can be applied;\index{formation rule}\index{rule!formation}
\item some \define{introduction rules}, stating how to inhabit the type;\index{introduction rule}\index{rule!introduction}
\item \define{elimination rules}, or an induction principle, stating how to use an
element of the type;
\index{induction principle}\index{eliminator}
\item \define{computation rules}, which are judgmental equalities explaining what happens when elimination rules are applied to results of introduction rules;
\index{computation rule}
\indexsee{rule!computation}{computation rule}
\item optional \define{uniqueness principles}, which are judgmental equalities explaining how every element of the type is uniquely determined by the results of elimination rules applied to it.
\index{uniqueness!principle}
\indexsee{principle!uniqueness}{uniqueness principle}
\end{itemize}
(See also \cref{rmk:introducing-new-concepts}.)
For the dependent function type these rules are:
%
\begin{mathparpagebreakable}
\def\premise{\oftp{\Gamma}{A}{\UU_i} \and \oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{B}{\UU_i}}
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\form]
\premise
{\oftp\Gamma{\tprd{x:A}B}{\UU_i}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\intro]
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{b}{B}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\lam{x:A} b}{\tprd{x:A} B}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\elim]
{\oftp\Gamma{f}{\tprd{x:A} B} \\ \oftp\Gamma{a}{A}}
{\oftp\Gamma{f(a)}{B[a/x]}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\comp]
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{b}{B} \\ \oftp\Gamma{a}{A}}
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{(\lam{x:A} b)(a)}{b[a/x]}{B[a/x]}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\uniq]
{\oftp\Gamma{f}{\tprd{x:A} B}}
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{f}{(\lamu{x:A}f(x))}{\tprd{x:A} B}}
\end{mathparpagebreakable}
The expression $\lam{x:A} b$ binds free occurrences of $x$ in $b$, as does $\tprd{x:A} B$ for
$B$.
When $x$ does not occur freely in $B$ so that $B$ does not depend on $A$, we obtain as a
special case the ordinary function type $A\to B \defeq \tprd{x:A} B$. We take this as the \emph{definition} of $\to$.
We may abbreviate an expression $\lam{x:A} b$ as $\lamu{x:A} b$, with the understanding
that the omitted type $A$ should be filled in appropriately before type-checking.
\subsection{Dependent pair types (\texorpdfstring{$\Sigma$}{Σ}-types)}
\label{sec:more-formal-sigma}
\index{type!dependent pair}%
\index{type!product}%
In \cref{sec:sigma-types}, we needed $\to$ and $\prdsym$ types in order to
define the introduction and elimination rules for $\smsym$; as with $\prdsym$, contexts allow us to state the rules for $\smsym$ independently.
Recall that the elimination rule for a positive type such as $\Sigma$ is called \emph{induction} and denoted by $\ind{}$.
%
\begin{mathparpagebreakable}
\def\premise{\oftp{\Gamma}{A}{\UU_i} \and \oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{B}{\UU_i}}
\inferrule*[right=$\Sigma$-\form]
\premise
{\oftp\Gamma{\tsm{x:A} B}{\UU_i}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\Sigma$-\intro]
{\oftp{\Gamma, \tmtp x A}{B}{\UU_i} \\
\oftp\Gamma{a}{A} \\ \oftp\Gamma{b}{B[a/x]}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\tup ab}{\tsm{x:A} B}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\Sigma$-\elim]
{\oftp{\Gamma, \tmtp z {\tsm{x:A} B}}{C}{\UU_i} \\
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp x A,\tmtp y B}{g}{C[\tup x y/z]} \\
\oftp\Gamma{p}{\tsm{x:A} B}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\ind{\tsm{x:A} B}(z.C,x.y.g,p)}{C[p/z]}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\Sigma$-\comp]
{\oftp{\Gamma, \tmtp z {\tsm{x:A} B}}{C}{\UU_i} \\
\oftp{\Gamma, \tmtp x A, \tmtp y B}{g}{C[\tup x y/z]} \\\\
\oftp\Gamma{a'}{A} \\ \oftp\Gamma{b'}{B[a'/x]}}
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\ind{\tsm{x:A} B}(z.C,x.y.g,\tup{a'}{b'})}{g[a',b'/x,y]}{C[\tup {a'} {b'}/z]}}
\end{mathparpagebreakable}
%
The expression $\tsm{x:A} B$ binds free occurrences of $x$ in $B$. Furthermore, because
$\ind{\tsm{x:A} B}$ has some arguments with free variables beyond those in $\Gamma$,
we bind (following the variable names above) $z$ in $C$, and $x$ and $y$ in $g$.
These bindings are written as $z.C$ and $x.y.g$, to indicate the names of the bound
variables.
\index{variable!bound}%
In particular, we treat $\ind{\tsm{x:A} B}$ as a primitive,
two of whose arguments contain binders; this is superficially similar to, but
different from, $\ind{\tsm{x:A} B}$ being a function that takes functions as
arguments.
When $B$ does not contain free occurrences of $x$, we obtain as a special case
the cartesian product $A \times B \defeq \tsm{x:A} B$. We take this
as the \emph{definition} of the cartesian product.
Notice that we don't postulate a judgmental uniqueness principle for $\Sigma$-types, even
though we could have; see \cref{thm:eta-sigma} for a proof of the corresponding
propositional uniqueness principle.
\subsection{Coproduct types}
\index{type!coproduct}%
\begin{mathparpagebreakable}
\inferrule*[right=$+$-\form]
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ \oftp\Gamma{B}{\UU_i}}
{\oftp\Gamma{A+B}{\UU_i}}
\\
\inferrule*[right=$+$-\intro${}_1$]
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ \oftp\Gamma{B}{\UU_i} \\\\ \oftp\Gamma{a}{A}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\inl(a)}{A+B}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$+$-\intro${}_2$]
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ \oftp\Gamma{B}{\UU_i} \\\\ \oftp\Gamma{b}{B}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\inr(b)}{A+B}}
\\
\inferrule*[right=$+$-\elim]
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp z{(A+B)}}{C}{\UU_i} \\\\
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{c}{C[\inl(x)/z]} \\
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp yB}{d}{C[\inr(y)/z]} \\\\
\oftp\Gamma{e}{A+B}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\ind{A+B}(z.C,x.c,y.d,e)}{C[e/z]}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$+$-\comp${}_1$]
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp z{(A+B)}}{C}{\UU_i} \\
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{c}{C[\inl(x)/z]} \\
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp yB}{d}{C[\inr(y)/z]} \\\\
\oftp\Gamma{a}{A}}
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\ind{A+B}(z.C,x.c,y.d,\inl(a))}{c[a/x]}{C[\inl(a)/z]}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$+$-\comp${}_2$]
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp z{(A+B)}}{C}{\UU_i} \\
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA}{c}{C[\inl(x)/z]} \\
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp yB}{d}{C[\inr(y)/z]} \\\\
\oftp\Gamma{b}{B}}
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\ind{A+B}(z.C,x.c,y.d,\inr(b))}{d[b/y]}{C[\inr(b)/z]}}
\end{mathparpagebreakable}
%
In $\ind{A+B}$, $z$ is bound in $C$, $x$ is bound in $c$, and $y$ is bound in
$d$.
\subsection{The empty type \texorpdfstring{$\emptyt$}{0}}
\index{type!empty|(}%
\begin{mathparpagebreakable}
\inferrule*[right=$\emptyt$-\form]
{\wfctx\Gamma}
{\oftp\Gamma\emptyt{\UU_i}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\emptyt$-\elim]
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp x\emptyt}{C}{\UU_i} \\ \oftp\Gamma{a}{\emptyt}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\ind{\emptyt}(x.C,a)}{C[a/x]}}
\end{mathparpagebreakable}
%
In $\ind{\emptyt}$, $x$ is bound in $C$. The empty type has no introduction rule and no computation rule.
\index{type!empty|)}%
\subsection{The unit type \texorpdfstring{$\unit$}{1}}
\label{sec:more-formal-unit}
\index{type!unit|(}%
\begin{mathparpagebreakable}
\inferrule*[right=$\unit$-\form]
{\wfctx\Gamma}
{\oftp\Gamma\unit{\UU_i}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\unit$-\intro]
{\wfctx\Gamma}
{\oftp\Gamma{\ttt}{\unit}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\unit$-\elim]
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp x\unit}{C}{\UU_i} \\
\oftp{\Gamma}{c}{C[\ttt/x]} \\
\oftp\Gamma{a}{\unit}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\ind{\unit}(x.C,c,a)}{C[a/x]}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\unit$-\comp]
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp x\unit}{C}{\UU_i} \\
\oftp{\Gamma}{c}{C[\ttt/x]}}
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\ind{\unit}(x.C,c,\ttt)}{c}{C[\ttt/x]}}
\end{mathparpagebreakable}
%
In $\ind{\unit}$ the variable $x$ is bound in $C$.
Notice that we do not postulate a judgmental uniqueness principle for the unit
type; see \cref{sec:finite-product-types} for a proof of the corresponding
propositional uniqueness statement.
\index{type!unit|)}%
\subsection{The natural number type}
\index{natural numbers|(}%
We give the rules for natural numbers, following \cref{sec:inductive-types}.
\begin{mathparpagebreakable}
\def\premise{
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp x{\N}}{C}{\UU_i} \\
\oftp\Gamma{c_0}{C[0/x]} \\
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp{x}\N,\tmtp y C}{c_s}{C[\suc(x)/x]}}
%
\inferrule*[right=$\N$-\form]
{\wfctx\Gamma}
{\oftp\Gamma{\N}{\UU_i}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\N$-\intro${}_1$]
{\wfctx\Gamma}
{\oftp\Gamma{0}{\N}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\N$-\intro${}_2$]
{\oftp\Gamma{n}{\N}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\suc(n)}{\N}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\N$-\elim]
{\premise \\ \oftp\Gamma{n}{\N}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\ind{\N}(x.C,c_0,x.y.c_s,n)}{C[n/x]}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\N$-\comp${}_1$]
{\premise}
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\ind{\N}(x.C,c_0,x.y.c_s,0)}{c_0}{C[0/x]}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\N$-\comp${}_2$]
{\premise \\ \oftp\Gamma{n}{\N}}
{\Gamma\vdash
{\begin{aligned}[t]
&\ind{\N}(x.C,c_0,x.y.c_s,\suc(n)) \\
&\quad \jdeq c_s[n,\ind{\N}(x.C,c_0,x.y.c_s,n)/x,y] : C[\suc(n)/x]
\end{aligned}}}
\end{mathparpagebreakable}
%
In $\ind{\N}$, $x$ is bound in $C$, and $x$ and $y$ are bound in $c_s$.
Other inductively defined types follow the same general scheme.
\index{natural numbers|)}%
\subsection{Identity types}
\label{sec:more-formal-identity}
\index{type!identity|(}%
The presentation here corresponds to the (unbased) path induction principle for identity types in
\cref{sec:identity-types}.
\begin{mathparpagebreakable}
\inferrule*[right=$\idsym$-\form]
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ \oftp\Gamma{a}{A} \\ \oftp\Gamma{b}{A}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\id[A]{a}{b}}{\UU_i}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\idsym$-\intro]
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\ \oftp\Gamma{a}{A}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\refl a}{\id[A]aa}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\idsym$-\elim]
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA,\tmtp yA,\tmtp p{\id[A]xy}}{C}{\UU_i} \\
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp zA}{c}{C[z,z,\refl z/x,y,p]} \\
\oftp\Gamma{a}{A} \\ \oftp\Gamma{b}{A} \\ \oftp\Gamma{p'}{\id[A]ab}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\indid{A}(x.y.p.C,z.c,a,b,p')}{C[a,b,p'/x,y,p]}}
\and
\inferrule*[right=$\idsym$-\comp]
{\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp xA,\tmtp yA,\tmtp p{\id[A]xy}}{C}{\UU_i} \\
\oftp{\Gamma,\tmtp zA}{c}{C[z,z,\refl z/x,y,p]} \\
\oftp\Gamma{a}{A}}
{\jdeqtp\Gamma{\indid{A}(x.y.p.C,z.c,a,a,\refl a)}{c[a/z]}{C[a,a,\refl a/x,y,p]}}
\end{mathparpagebreakable}
%
In $\indid{A}$, $x$, $y$, and $p$ are bound in $C$, and $z$ is bound in
$c$.
\index{type!identity|)}%
\subsection{Definitions}
\index{definition}%
Although the rules we listed so far allows us to construct everything we need directly, we
would still like to be able to use named constants, such as $\isequiv$, as a matter of
convenience. Informally, we can think of these constants simply as
abbreviations, but the situation is a bit subtler in the formalization.
For example, consider function composition, which takes $f:A\to B$ and
$g:B\to C$ to $g\circ f:A\to C$. Somewhat unexpectedly, to make this work formally, $\circ$ must take as arguments not only $f$ and $g$, but also their types $A$, $B$, $C$:
%
\begin{narrowmultline*}
{\circ} \defeq \lam{A:\UU_i}{B:\UU_i}{C:\UU_i}
\narrowbreak
\lam{g:B\to C}{f:A\to B}{x:A} g(f(x)).
\end{narrowmultline*}
%
From a practical perspective, we do not want to annotate each application of
$\circ$ with $A$, $B$ and $C$, as the are usually quite easily guessed from surrounding information. We would like to simply write $g\circ f$.
Then, strictly speaking, $g \circ f$ is not an abbreviation for $\lam{x : A} g(f(x))$,
because it involves additional \define{implicit arguments} which we want to suppress.
\index{implicit argument}
Inference of implicit arguments, typical ambiguity\index{typical ambiguity} (\cref{sec:universes}),
ensuring that symbols are only defined once, etc., are collectively called
\define{elaboration}. \index{elaboration, in type theory}
Elaboration must take place prior to checking a derivation, and is
thus not usually presented as part of the core type theory. However, it is
essentially impossible to use any implementation of type theory which does not
perform elaboration; see \cite{Coq,norell2007towards} for further discussion.
\section{Homotopy type theory}
\label{sec:hott-features}
In this section we state the additional axioms of homotopy type theory which distinguish it from standard Martin-L\"{o}f type theory: function extensionality, the
univalence axiom, and higher inductive types. We state them in the style
of the second presentation \cref{sec:syntax-more-formally}, although the first presentation \cref{sec:syntax-informally} could be used just as well.
\subsection{Function extensionality and univalence}
There are two basic ways of introducing axioms which do not introduce new syntax or judgmental equalities (function extensionality and univalence are of this form):
either add a primitive constant to inhabit the axiom, or prove all theorems which depend on the axiom by hypothesizing a variable that inhabits the axiom, cf.\ \cref{sec:axioms}.
While these are essentially equivalent, we opt for the former approach because we feel that the axioms of homotopy type theory are an essential part of the core theory.
\index{function extensionality}%
\cref{axiom:funext} is formalized by introduction of a constant $\funext$ which
asserts that $\happly$ is an equivalence:
%
\begin{mathparpagebreakable}
\inferrule*[right=$\Pi$-\textsc{ext}]
{\oftp\Gamma{f}{\tprd{x:A} B} \\
\oftp\Gamma{g}{\tprd{x:A} B}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\funext(f,g)}{\isequiv(\happly_{f,g})}}
\end{mathparpagebreakable}
%
The definitions of $\happly$ and $\isequiv$ can be found in~\eqref{eq:happly} and
\cref{sec:concluding-remarks}, respectively.
\index{univalence axiom}%
\cref{axiom:univalence} is formalized in a similar fashion, too:
%
\begin{mathparpagebreakable}
\inferrule*[right=$\UU_i$-\textsc{univ}]
{\oftp\Gamma{A}{\UU_i} \\
\oftp\Gamma{B}{\UU_i}}
{\oftp\Gamma{\univalence(A,B)}{\isequiv(\idtoeqv_{A,B})}}
\end{mathparpagebreakable}
%
The definition of $\idtoeqv$ can be found in~\eqref{eq:uidtoeqv}.
\subsection{The circle}
\index{type!circle}%
Here we give an example of a basic higher inductive type; others follow the same
general scheme, albeit with elaborations.