-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
Copy pathAnalytic_WordandObject_1964.txt
9999 lines (9099 loc) · 715 KB
/
Analytic_WordandObject_1964.txt
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
Página 1 de 200
Word and Object
Willard Van Orman Quine
Edgar Pierce Professor of Philosophy
Harvard University
-iiiCOPYRIGHT © 1960
BY
THE MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY
All Rights Reserved
This book or any part thereof must not be reproduced in any form without the written permission of
the publisher.
Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 60-9621
PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA
-ivTo
RUDOLF CARNAP
Teacher and Friend
-v-viWie Schiffer sind wir, die ihr Schiff auf offener See umbauen müssen, ohne es jemals in einem Dock
zerlegen und aus besten Bestandteilen neu errichten zu können.
-- OTTO NEURATH
Ontology recapitulates philology.
-- JAMES GRIER MILLER
-vii-viii-
Preface
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 2 de 200
Language is a social art. In acquiring it we have to depend entirely on intersubjectively available
cues as to what to say and when. Hence there is no justification for collating linguistic meanings,
unless in terms of men's dispositions to respond overtly to socially observable stimulations. An effect
of recognizing this limitation is that the enterprise of translation is found to be involved in a certain
systematic indeterminacy; and this is the main theme of Chapter II.
The indeterminacy of translation invests even the question what objects to construe a term as true of.
Studies of the semantics of reference consequently turn out to make sense only when directed upon
substantially our language, from within. But we do remain free to reflect, thus parochially, on the
development and structure of our own referential apparatus; and this I do in ensuing chapters. In so
doing one encounters various anomalies and conflicts that are implicit in this apparatus (Chapter IV),
and is moved to adopt remedies in the spirit of modern logic (Chapters V and VI). Clarity also is
perhaps gained on what we do when we impute existence, and what considerations may best guide
such decisions; thus Chapter VII.
My six Gavin David Young Lectures in Philosophy at the University of Adelaide, June 1959, will
have consisted of portions of this book. Similarly for various of my lectures at the University of
Tokyo in July and August. An abridgment of the last chapter figured as the Howison Lecture in
Philosophy at the University of California in Berkeley, May 1959, and parts of Chapters II through
-ixVI went to make up five lectures that I gave at Stanford University in April.
A year earlier I drew on the work in progress for my paper at the fourth Colloque Philosophique de
Royaumont and for my presidential address to the Eastern Division of the American Philosophical
Association. The year before that, 1956-57, I presented portions of interim versions of Chapter II as
single lectures at four institutions: Princeton University, the Institute for Advanced Study, Columbia
University, and the University of Pennsylvania. My course in the philosophy of language, which I
have given ten times at Harvard since VJ-day, has represented ten phases in the development of the
book; and a further intervening phase was represented by courses that I gave at Oxford as George
Eastman Visiting Professor in 1953-54 and by my A. T. Shearman Lectures at University College,
London, in 1954.
Three publications overlap the present text of the book, having stemmed from the work in progress.
Two of them are indicated at the beginnings of §§ 7 and 19. The third is "Le mythe de la
signification," presumed forthcoming in the acts of the Royaumont colloquium. Three further recent
papers bear mention as having conveyed some of the developing notions of the book in other
phrasing. One is "The scope and language of science," which formed part of the Columbia
Bicentennial program in 1954 and appeared in the British Journal for the Philosophy of Science in
1957. The others are "Quantifiers and propositional attitudes," Journal of Philosophy, 1956, and
"Logical truth", in Hook's American Philosophers at Work.
The benefits of a Harvard sabbatical, combined with a generous grant in aid from the Institute for
Advanced Study at Princeton, enabled me to devote the year 1956-57 to the book as a member of
that Institute. Similar generosity on the part of the Ford Foundation enabled me to devote the year
1958-59 to the same effort, as a Fellow of the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences
at Stanford. I gratefully acknowledge all this support. In addition I have the Rockefeller Foundation
to thank for a grant which provided secretarial help in keeping up the flow of typescript during years
when the secretarial services of the Institute and the Center were not at my disposal.
Last winter I enjoyed the close collaboration of Donald Davidson, who studied drafts of the book
and gave me the benefit of his able criticism and his knowledge of the literature. The book has
gained
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 3 de 200
-xmuch from his help, and much also, in its first half, from the wise scrutiny of my colleague Burton
Dreben. At various points in the book I have been helped also by advice and criticism from many
other friends, including J. L. Austin, C. A. Baylis, L. J. Binkley, Alonzo Church, J. C. Cooley,
Raymond Firth, Nelson Goodman, Joseph Greenberg, H. P. Grice, C. G. Hempel, Roman Jakobson,
J. A. Jenkins, Georg Kreisel, T. S. Kuhn, C. E. Osgood, Hilary Putnam, P. F. Strawson, Morton
White, Oscar Zariski, and Paul Ziff. I am grateful further to Jakobson for frequent encouragement
and varied helpfulness in his capacity of editor of this series.
W ILLARD AN O RMAN Q UINE V
Stanford, California
June 3, 1959
-xi-xii-
Contents
Chapter I. Language and Truth
1
5
9
13
17
21
1 Beginning with ordinary things
2 The objective pull; or, e pluribus unum
3 The interanimation of sentences
4 Ways of learning words
5 Evidence
6 Posits and truth
Chapter II. Translation and Meaning
26
31
35
40
46
51
57
61
68
73
7 First steps of radical translation
8 Stimulation and stimulus meaning
9 Occasion sentences. Intrusive information
10 Observation sentences
11 Intrasubjective synonymy of occasion sentences
12 Synonymy of terms
13 Translating logical connectives
14 Synonymous and analytic sentences
15 Analytical hypotheses
16 On failure to perceive the indeterminacy
-xiii-
Chapter III. The Ontogenesis of Reference
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 4 de 200
17 Words and qualities
18 Phonetic norms
19 Divided reference
20 Predication
21 Demonstratives. Attributives
22 Relative terms. Four phases of reference
23 Relative clauses. Indefinite singular terms
24 Identity
25 Abstract terms
80
85
90
95
100
105
110
114
118
Chapter IV. Vagaries of Reference
125
129
134
138
141
146
151
26 Vagueness
27 Ambiguity of terms
28 Some ambiguities of syntax
29 Ambiguity of scope
30 Referential opacity
31 Opacity and indefinite terms
32 Opacity in certain verbs
Chapter V. Regimentation
33 Aims and claims of regimentation
34 Quantifiers and other operators
35 Variables and referential opacity
36 Time. Confinement of general terms
37 Names reparsed
38 Conciliatory remarks. Elimination of singular terms
39 Definition and the double life
157
161
166
170
176
181
186
Chapter VI. Flight from Intension
40 Propositions and eternal sentences
41 Modality
191
195
-xiv42 Propositions as meanings
43 Toward dispensing with intensional objects
44 Other objects for the attitudes
45 The double standard
46 Dispositions and conditionals
47 A framework for theory
200
206
211
216
222
226
Chapter VII. Ontic Decision
48 Nominalism and realism
49 False predilections. Ontic commitment
50 Entia non grata
51 Limit myths
52 Geometrical objects
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
233
238
243
248
251
28/4/2007
Página 5 de 200
53 The ordered pair as philosophical paradigm
54 Numbers, mind, and body
55 Whither classes?
56 Semantic ascent
Bibliographical References
Index
257
262
266
270
277
287
-xv-xvi-
CHAPTER ONE
Language and Truth
§ 1. BEGINNING WITH ORDINARY THINGS
This familiar desk manifests its presence by resisting my pressures and by deflecting light to my
eyes. Physical things generally, however remote, become known to us only through the effects which
they help to induce at our sensory surfaces. Yet our common-sense talk of physical things goes
forward without benefit of explanations in more intimately sensory terms. Entification begins at
arm's length; the points of condensation in the primordial conceptual scheme are things glimpsed,
not glimpses. In this there is little cause for wonder. Each of us learns his language from other
people, through the observable mouthing of words under conspicuously intersubjective
circumstances. Linguistically, and hence conceptually, the things in sharpest focus are the things that
are public enough to be talked of publicly, common and conspicuous enough to be talked of often,
and near enough to sense to be quickly identified and learned by name; it is to these that words apply
first and foremost.
Talk of subjective sense qualities comes mainly as a derivative idiom. When one tries to describe a
particular sensory quality, he typically resorts to reference to public things -- describing a color as
orange or heliotrope, a smell as like that of rotten eggs. Just as one sees his nose best in a mirror,
removed to half the optimum focal distance, so also he best identifies his sense data by reflecting
them in external objects.
Impressed with the fact that we know external things only mediately through our senses,
philosophers from Berkeley onward have
-1undertaken to strip away the physicalistic conjectures and bare the sense data. Yet even as we try to
recapture the data, in all their innocence of interpretation, we find ourselves depending upon
sidelong glances into natural science. We may hold, with Berkeley, that the momentary data of
vision consist of colors disposed in a spatial manifold of two dimensions; but we come to this
conclusion by reasoning from the bidimensionality of the ocular surface, or by noting the illusions
which can be engendered by two-dimensional artifacts such as paintings and mirrors, or, more
abstractly, simply by noting that the interception of light in space must necessarily take place along a
surface. Again we may hold that the momentary data of audition are clusters of components each of
which is a function of just two variables, pitch and loudness; but not without knowledge of the
physical variables of frequency and amplitude in the stimulating string.
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 6 de 200
The motivating insight, viz. that we can know external things only through impacts at our nerve
endings, is itself based on our general knowledge of the ways of physical objects -- illuminated
desks, reflected light, activated retinas. Small wonder that the quest for sense data should be guided
by the same sort of knowledge that prompts it.
Aware of the points thus far set forth, our philosopher may still try, in a spirit of rational
reconstruction, to abstract out a pure stream of sense experience and then depict physical doctrine as
a means of systematizing the regularities discernible in the stream. He may imagine an ideal
"protocol language" which, even if in fact learned after common-sense talk of physical things or not
at all, is evidentially prior: a fancifully fancyless medium of unvarnished news. Talk of ordinary
physical things he would then see as, in principle, a device for simplifying that disorderly account of
the passing show.
But this is a misleading way of depicting matters, even when the idea of a sense-datum "language" is
counted frankly as metaphor. For the trouble is that immediate experience simply will not, of itself,
cohere as an autonomous domain. References to physical things are largely what hold it together.
These references are not just inessential vestiges of the initially intersubjective character of language,
capable of being weeded out by devising an artificially subjective language for sense data. Rather
they give us our main continuing access to past sense data themselves; for past sense
-2data are mostly gone for good except as commemorated in physical posits. All we would have apart
from posits and speculation are present sense data and present memories of past ones; and a memory
trace of a sense datum is too meager an affair to do much good. Actual memories mostly are traces
not of past sensations but of past conceptualization or verbalization. 1
There is every reason to inquire into the sensory or stimulatory background of ordinary talk of
physical things. The mistake comes only in seeking an implicit sub-basement of conceptualization,
or of language. Conceptualization on any considerable scale is inseparable from language, and our
ordinary language of physical things is about as basic as language gets.
Neurath has likened science to a boat which, if we are to rebuild it, we must rebuild plank by plank
while staying afloat in it. The philosopher and the scientist are in the same boat. If we improve our
understanding of ordinary talk of physical things, it will not be by reducing that talk to a more
familiar idiom; there is none. It will be by clarifying the connections, causal or otherwise, between
ordinary talk of physical things and various further matters which in turn we grasp with help of
ordinary talk of physical things.
On the face of it there is a certain verbal perversity in the idea that ordinary talk of familiar physical
things is not in large part understood as it stands, or that the familiar physical things are not real, or
that evidence for their reality needs to be uncovered. For surely the key words 'understood', 'real',
and 'evidence' here are too ill-defined to stand up under such punishment. We should only be
depriving them of the very denotations to which they mainly owe such sense as they make to us. It
was a lexicographer, Dr. Johnson, who demonstrated the reality of a stone by kicking it; and to begin
with, at least, we have little better to go on than Johnsonian usage. The familiar material objects may
not be all that is real, but they are admirable examples.
There are, however, philosophers who overdo this line of thought, treating ordinary language as
sacrosanct. They exalt ordinary language to the exclusion of one of its own traits: its disposition to
keep on evolving. Scientific neologism is itself just linguistic evolution gone self-conscious, as
science is self-conscious common sense. And philosophy in turn, as an effort to get clearer on things,
is not
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 7 de 200
____________________
1See Chisholm, Perceiving, p. 160.
-3to be distinguished in essential points of purpose and method from good and bad science.
In particular we shall find, as we get on with organizing and adjusting various of the turns of phrase
that participate in what pass for affirmations of existence, that certain of these take on key
significance in the increasingly systematic structure; and then, reacting in a manner typical of
scientific behavior, we shall come to favor these idioms as the existence affirmations "strictly socalled." One could even end up, though we ourselves shall not, by finding that the smoothest and
most adequate overall account of the world does not after all accord existence to ordinary physical
things, in that refined sense of existence. Such eventual departures from Johnsonian usage could
partake of the spirit of science and even of the evolutionary spirit of ordinary language itself.
Our boat stays afloat because at each alteration we keep the bulk of it intact as a going concern. Our
words continue to make passable sense because of continuity of change of theory: we warp usage
gradually enough to avoid rupture. And such, in the beginning, is the case for Johnsonian usage
itself, since our questioning of objects can coherently begin only in relation to a system of theory
which is itself predicated on our interim acceptances of objects.
We are limited in how we can start even if not in where we may end up. To vary Neurath's figure
with Wittgenstein's, we may kick away our ladder only after we have climbed it.
So the proposition that external things are ultimately to be known only through their action on our
bodies should be taken as one among various coordinate truths, in physics and elsewhere, about
initially unquestioned physical things. It qualifies the empirical meaning of our talk of physical
things, while not questioning the reference. There remains abundant reason to inquire more closely
into the empirical meaning or stimulatory conditions of our talk of physical things, for we learn in
this way about the scope of creative imagination in science; and such inquiry is none the worse for
being conducted within the framework of those same physical acceptations. No inquiry being
possible without some conceptual scheme, we may as well retain and use the best one we know right down to the latest detail of quantum mechanics, if we know it and it matters.
Analyze theory-building how we will, we all must start in the middle. Our conceptual firsts are
middle-sized, middle-distanced
-4objects, and our introduction to them and to everything comes midway in the cultural evolution of
the race. In assimilating this cultural fare we are little more aware of a distinction between report and
invention, substance and style, cues and conceptualization, than we are of a distinction between the
proteins and the carbohydrates of our material intake. Retrospectively we may distinguish the
components of theory-building, as we distinguish the proteins and carbohydrates while subsisting on
them. We cannot strip away the conceptual trappings sentence by sentence and leave a description of
the objective world; but we can investigate the world, and man as a part of it, and thus find out what
cues he could have of what goes on around him. Subtracting his cues from his world view, we get
man's net contribution as the difference. This difference marks the extent of man's conceptual
sovereignty -- the domain within which he can revise theory while saving the data.
In a general way, therefore, I propose in this introductory chapter to ponder our talk of physical
phenomena as a physical phenomenon, and our scientific imaginings as activities within the world
that we imagine. Later chapters will treat more closely of details.
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 8 de 200
§ 2. THE OBJECTIVE PULL; OR, E
PLURIBUS UNUM
'Ouch' is a one-word sentence which a man may volunteer from time to time by way of laconic
comment on the passing show. The correct occasions of its use are those attended by painful
stimulation. Such use of the word, like the correct use of language generally, is inculcated in the
individual by training on the part of society; and society achieves this despite not sharing the
individual's pain. Society's method is in principle that of rewarding the utterance of 'Ouch' when the
speaker shows some further evidence of sudden discomfort, say a wince, or is actually seen to suffer
violence, and of penalizing the utterance of 'Ouch' when the speaker is visibly untouched and his
countenance unruffled.
For the man who has learned his language lesson, some of the stimuli evocative of 'Ouch' may be
publicly visible blows and slashes, while others are hidden from the public eye in the depths of his
bowels. Society, acting solely on overt manifestations, has been able to train the individual to say the
socially proper thing in response even to socially undetectable stimulations. The trick has
-5depended on prior concomitances between covert stimulation and overt behavior, notably the
wincing instinct.
We can imagine a primitive use of 'Red' as a one-word sentence somewhat on a par with 'Ouch'. Just
as 'Ouch' is the appropriate remark on the occasion of painful stimulation, so 'Red', under the usage
which I am now imagining, is the appropriate remark on the occasion of those distinctive
photochemical effects which are wrought in one's retina by the impact of red light. This time
society's method of training consists in rewarding the utterance of 'Red' when the individual is seen
looking at something red, and penalizing it when he is seen looking at something else.
Actually the uses of 'Red' are less simple. Commonly 'red', unlike 'ouch', turns up as a fragment of
longer sentences. Moreover, even when 'Red' is used by itself as a one-word sentence, what evokes it
is usually not the mere apprehension of something red; more commonly there has been a verbal
stimulus, in the form of a question. But let us keep for a moment to the fictitious usage described in
the preceding paragraph; for it, by its similarity to 'Ouch', will help to bring out also a certain
contrast.
The critic, society's agent, approves the subject's utterance of 'Red' by observing the subject and his
viewed object and finding the latter red. In part, therefore, the critic's cue is red irradiation of his own
retina. A partial symmetry obtains between the subject's cue for utterance and the critic's cue for
approval in the case of 'Red', which, happily for the critic, was lacking in the case of 'Ouch'. The
partial symmetry in the one case, and the lack of it in the other, suggest a certain superficial sense in
which 'Ouch' may be spoken of as more subjective in reference than 'Red'; 'Red' more objective than
'Ouch'.
Exceptions are possible on either side. If the critic and the subject are fighting a fire and are scorched
by the same sudden gust, then the critic's approval of the subject's 'Ouch' does not differ significantly
from the imagined case of 'Red'. Conversely, a critic may approve a subject's 'Red' on indirect
evidence, failing to glimpse the object himself. If we call 'Ouch' more subjective than 'Red', we must
be taken as alluding thereby only to the most characteristic learning situations. In the case of 'Red',
typically one's mentor or critic sees red; in the case of 'Ouch', typically he does not get hurt.
'Ouch' is not independent of social training. One has only to
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 9 de 200
-6prick a foreigner to appreciate that it is an English word. But in its subjectivity it is a little unusual.
Words being social tools, objectivity counts toward their survival. When a word has considerable
currency despite the subjective twist, it may be expected, like the pronouns 'I' and 'you', to have a
valuable social function of some exceptional sort. The survival value of 'Ouch', from a social point of
view, is as a distress signal. And the word is of only marginal linguistic status, after all, being
incapable of integration into longer sentences.
The usual premium on objectivity is well illustrated by 'square'. Each of a party of observers glances
at a tile from his own vantage point and calls it square; and each of them has, as his retinal projection
of the tile, a scalene quadrilateral which is geometrically dissimilar to everyone else's. The learner of
'square' has to take his chances with the rest of society, and he ends up using the word to suit.
Association of 'square' with just the situations in which the retinal projection is square would be
simpler to learn, but the more objective usage is, by its very intersubjectivity, what we tend to be
exposed to and encouraged in.
In general, if a term is to be learned by induction from observed instances where it is applied, the
instances have to resemble one another in two ways: they have to be enough alike from the learner's
point of view, from occasion to occasion, to afford him a basis of similarity to generalize upon, and
they have to be enough alike from simultaneous distinct points of view to enable the teacher and
learner to share the appropriate occasions. A term restricted to squares normal to the line of sight
would meet the first requirement only; a term applying to physical squares in all their scalene
projections meets both. And it meets both in the same way, in that the points of view available to the
learner from occasion to occasion are likewise the points of view available to teacher and learner on
simultaneous occasions. Such is the way with terms for observable physical objects generally; and
thus it is that such objects are focal to reference and thought.
'Red', unlike 'square', is a happy case where a nearly uniform stimulatory condition is shared by
simultaneous observers. All the assembled retinas are irradiated by substantially the same red light,
whereas no two of them receive geometrically similar projections of the square. The pull toward
objectivity is thus a strong pull away from the subjectively simplest rule of association in the case of
-7'square', and much less so in the case of 'red'. Hence our readiness to think of color as more
subjective than physical shape. But some pull of the same kind occurs even in the case of 'red',
insofar as reflections from the environment cause the red object to cast somewhat different tints to
different points of view. The objective pull will regiment all the responses still as 'red', by activating
myriad corrective cues. These corrective cues are used unconsciously, such is the perfection of our
socialization; a painter has even to school himself to set them aside when he tries to reproduce his
true retinal intake.
The uniformity that unites us in communication and belief is a uniformity of resultant patterns
overlying a chaotic subjective diversity of connections between words and experience. Uniformity
comes where it matters socially; hence rather in point of intersubjectively conspicuous circumstances
of utterance than in point of privately conspicuous ones. For an extreme illustration of the point,
consider two men one of whom has normal color vision and the other of whom is color-blind as
between red and green. Society has trained both men by the method noted earlier: rewarding the
utterance of 'red' when the speaker is seen fixating something red, and penalizing it in the contrary
case. Moreover the gross socially observable results are about alike: both men are pretty good about
attributing 'red' to just the red things. But the private mechanisms by which the two men achieve
these similar results are very different. The one man has learned 'red' in association with the
regulation photochemical effect. The other man has painfully learned to be stimulated to 'red' by
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 10 de 200
light in various wavelengths (red and green) in company with elaborate special combinations of
supplementary conditions of intensity, saturation, shape, and setting, calculated e.g. to admit fire and
sunsets and to exclude grass; to admit blossoms and exclude leaves; and to admit lobsters only after
boiling.
Different persons growing up in the same language are like different bushes trimmed and trained to
take the shape of identical elephants. The anatomical details of twigs and branches will fulfill the
elephantine form differently from bush to bush, but the overall outward results are alike.
-8-
§ 3. THE INTERANIMATION OF
SENTENCES 1
'Ouch' was a one-word sentence. 'Red' and 'Square', when used in isolation in the ways lately
imagined, are likewise best looked upon as sentences. Most sentences are longer. But even a longer
sentence may still be learned as a single unit, like 'Ouch', 'Red', and 'Square', by a direct conditioning
of the whole utterance to some sensory stimulation. Characteristically Humean problems, of how we
acquire various ideas, may often be by-passed by representing the words in question simply as
fragments of sentences which were learned as wholes.
Not that all or most sentences are learned as wholes. Most sentences are built up rather from learned
parts, by analogy with the way in which those parts have previously been seen to occur in other
sentences which may or may not have been learned as wholes. 2 What sentences are got by such
analogical synthesis, and what ones are got directly, is a question of each individual's own forgotten
history.
It is evident how new sentences may be built from old materials and volunteered on appropriate
occasions simply by virtue of the analogies. Having been directly conditioned to the appropriate use
of 'Foot' (or 'This is my foot') as a sentence, and 'Hand' likewise, and 'My foot hurts' as a whole, the
child might conceivably utter 'My hand hurts' on an appropriate occasion, though unaided by
previous experience with that actual sentence.
But think how little we would be able to say if our learning of sentences were strictly limited to those
two modes: (1) learning sentences as wholes by a direct conditioning of them to appropriate nonverbal stimulations, and (2) producing further sentences from the foregoing ones by analogical
substitution as in the preceding paragraph. The sentences afforded by mode (1) are such that each
has its particular range of admissible stimulatory occasions, independently of wider context. The
sentences added by (2) are more of the same sort - learned faster thanks to (2), but no less capable of
being learned in mode (1). Speech thus confined would be strikingly like bare reporting of sense
data.
____________________
1The phrase is adapted from Richards.
2This process, and the primacy of the sentence, were already appreciated in ancient India. See
Brough, "Some Indian theories of meaning", pp. 164-167.
-9The objective pull described in § 2 would indeed be there. The stimulations eliciting 'It is square'
would indeed take in the odd lot of suitably circumstanced skew projections that social pressure
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 11 de 200
requires. Yet the effect of this objective pull by itself is superficial: a mere warping of the
pigeonholes; a gerrymandering, in the public interest, of the range of stimulations which each report
embraces. Our idiom would remain very much the inadequate sort of idiom imagined in § 1: the
fancifully fancyless medium of unvarnished news. As there remarked, there would be no access to
the past, beyond the negligible yield of an occasional memory trace of an unconceptualized
stimulation.
What more is needed in order to capitalize the riches of past experience is hinted in the remark (§ 1)
that actual memories are mostly traces not of past sensation but of past conceptualization. We cannot
rest with a running conceptualization of the unsullied stream of experience; what we need is a
sullying of the stream. Association of sentences is wanted not just with non-verbal stimulation, but
with other sentences, if we are to exploit finished conceptualizations and not just repeat them.
Mode (2) above is already, in a way, an associating of sentences with sentences; but only in too
restrained a way. Further interverbal associations are required which provide for the use of new
sentences without tying them, even derivatively, to any fixed ranges of non-verbal stimuli.
The most obvious case of the verbal stimulation of verbal response is interrogation. It was already
remarked in § 2 that 'Red' as a one-word sentence usually needs a question for its elicitation. The
question may be simply 'What color is this?'. In this case the stimulus eliciting 'Red' is a compound
one: the red light assails the eye and the question the ear. Or the question may be 'What color will
you have?' or 'What color did it use to be?'. In such a case the stimulus eliciting 'Red' is the verbal
one unaccompanied by red light; though its power to elicit 'Red' depends, of course, on an earlier
association of 'Red' with red light.
The opposite dependence is also common: the power of a nonverbal stimulus to elicit a given
sentence commonly depends on earlier associations of sentences with sentences. And in fact it is
cases of this kind that best illustrate how language transcends the confines of essentially
phenomenalistic reporting. Thus someone mixes the contents of two test tubes, observes a green tint,
and says
-10'There was copper in it.' Here the sentence is elicited by a nonverbal stimulus, but the stimulus
depends for its efficacy upon an earlier network of associations of words with words; viz., one's
learning of chemical theory. Here we have a good glimpse of our workaday conceptual scheme as a
going concern. Here, as at the crude stage of (1) and (2), the sentence is elicited by a non-verbal
stimulus; but here, in contrast to that crude stage, the verbal network of an articulate theory has
intervened to link the stimulus with the response.
The intervening theory is composed of sentences associated with one another in multifarious ways
not easily reconstructed even in conjecture. There are so-called logical connections, and there are socalled causal ones; but any such interconnections of sentences must finally be due to the
conditioning of sentences as responses to sentences as stimuli. If some of the connections count more
particularly as logical or as causal, they do so only by reference to socalled logical or causal laws
which in turn are sentences within the theory. The theory as a whole-a chapter of chemistry, in this
case, plus relevant adjuncts from logic and elsewhere-is a fabric of sentences variously associated to
one another and to non-verbal stimuli by the mechanism of conditioned response.
Theory may be deliberate, as in a chapter on chemistry, or it may be second nature, as is the
immemorial doctrine of ordinary enduring middle-sized physical objects. In either case, theory
causes a sharing, by sentences, of sensory supports. In an arch, an overhead block is supported
immediately by other overhead blocks, and ultimately by all the base blocks collectively and none
individually; and so it is with sentences, when theoretically fitted. The contact of block to block is
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 12 de 200
the association of sentence to sentence, and the base blocks are sentences conditioned in the modes
(1) and (2) to non-verbal stimuli. Perhaps we should think of the arch as tottering on an earthquake;
thus even a base block is supported, now and again, only by the other base blocks via the arch. 3
Our example 'There is copper in it' is an overhead block, along with 'Copper oxide is green' and
others. One of the base blocks is perhaps the sentence 'The stuff has gone green', a sentence directly
conditioned to the sensory stimulation got from the test tube.
____________________
3The analogies of the fabric and the arch are well supplemented by the more detailed analogy of
the net which Hempel develops, Fundamentals of Concept Formation, p. 36.
-11In the series of sentence-to-sentence associations ultimately linking 'The stuff has gone green' with
'There was copper in it', all steps but the last are evidently unspoken. Some may be sketchily and
inaudibly spoken, but more are just skipped as the theory becomes second nature. Such skipping,
which exceeds the arch analogy, seems a basically humdrum affair: a transitivity of conditioning.
Another point that exceeds the arch analogy is the difference between occasion sentences like 'There
was copper in it', true anew for each of various experimental occasions (§ 9), and eternal sentences
like 'Copper oxide is green', true for good (§ 40). The occasion sentence is elicited from the
practicing chemist time and again. The eternal sentence may well be elicited from him just once, in
his youth, by the university examiner. The eternal ones tend most of all to drop out under the
transitivity of conditioning, leaving no trace except implicitly in the patterning of conditioning of
residual sentences.
What comes of the association of sentences with sentences is a vast verbal structure which, primarily
as a whole, is multifariously linked to non-verbal stimulation. These links attach to separate
sentences (for each person), but the same sentences are so bound up in turn with one another and
with further sentences that the nonverbal attachments themselves may stretch or give way under
strain. 4 In an obvious way this structure of interconnected sentences is a single connected fabric
including all sciences, and indeed everything we ever say about the world; for the logical truths at
least, and no doubt many more commonplace sentences too, are
____________________
4Aldrich has vividly summarized and criticized my view of these matters, in part as follows:
"Amplifying and modifying his own image of the universe of discourse as a field of force
bounded by 'experience' of the 'external world' ..., I suggest, in view of some of Quine's remarks,
that there are two forces that interpenetrate or fuse to constitute the field: the 'empirical' force
extending into the field from 'outside' and thus being stronger near the periphery; and the formal
or logical force, whose principle is simplicity and symmetry of laws, radiating out from the
center.... But in another and contrary vein Quine...seems to say...that the external or empirical
force is operative only at the edge, 'from outside.' Inside, the central force for simplicity,
convenience, and elegance has a field day, all by itself" (pp. 18 f.). What he misses in this
engaging last remark is that the peripheral sentences, those most firmly linked to non-verbal
stimulations, are linked also to other sentences; and thus it is that the external force is
communicated inward. On this duality of forces, see further the bipolar representation in Smith.
-12germane to all topics and thus provide connections. 5 However, some middle-sized scrap of theory
usually will embody all the connections that are likely to affect our adjudication of a given sentence.
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 13 de 200
The firmness of association to non-verbal stimuli, the power of such association to withstand the
contrary pull of a body of theory, grades off from one sentence to another. Roughly imaginable
sequences of nerve hits can confirm us in the statement that there is a brick house on Elm Street,
beyond the power of secondary associations to add or detract. Even where the conditioning to nonverbal stimulation is so firm, however, there is no telling to what extent it is original and to what
extent it results from a shortcutting, by transitivity of conditioning, of old connections of sentences
with sentences. Beneath the uniformity that unites us in communication there is a chaotic personal
diversity of connections, and, for each of us, the connections continue to evolve. No two of us learn
our language alike, nor, in a sense, does any finish learning it while he lives.
§ 4. WAYS OF LEARNING WORDS
At the beginning of § 3 we noted the contrast between learning sentences as wholes and building
them of parts. The first ones learned are learned as wholes, we saw, some being indeed oneword
sentences. As the child progresses, he tends increasingly to build his new sentences from parts; and
thus it is that one usually speaks of learning a new word rather than a new sentence. But even the
sophisticated learning of a new word is commonly a matter of learning it in context -- hence
learning, by example and analogy, the usage of sentences in which the word can occur. It therefore
remained appropriate, throughout § 3 and not just at the beginning of it, to treat sentences and not
words as the wholes whose use is learned -- though never denying that the learning of these wholes
proceeds largely by an abstracting and assembling of parts. Now let us think more specifically about
the parts.
What counts as a word, as against a string of two or more, is less evident than what counts as a
sentence. The principles behind the printer's use of spaces are dim, and the relevance of such
principles to any considerations of our own is doubly so. We
____________________
5This point has been lost sight of, I think, by some who have objected to an excessive holism
espoused in occasional brief passages of mine. Even so, I think their objections largely warranted.
See e.g. Hofstadter, pp. 408 ff.
-13might even be tempted to throw printers' precedent to the winds and call any sentence a word, on a
par with 'Ouch', if it is learned as a whole rather than by building from parts. But this plan is poor; it
would cause wordhood to vary capriciously from person to person and it would make wordhood for
each person a function of his own forgotten infantile history. Actually no rationalization of the word
will be needed here. Printers' practice, however accidental, gives the word 'word' a denotation good
enough for anything that I shall have to say.
The learning of words, in this rough and ready sense of the word, partakes of a contrast correlative to
that between learning sentences as wholes and building them of parts. In the case of words it is a
contrast between learning a word in isolation -- i.e., in effect, as a one-word sentence -- and learning
it contextually, or by abstraction, as a fragment of sentences learned as wholes. Prepositions,
conjunctions, and many other words are bound to have been learned only contextually; we get on to
using them by analogy with the ways in which they have been seen to turn up in past sentences. It is
mostly just substantives, adjectives, and verbs that will occasionally have been learned in isolation.
Which of them are learned thus, and which only contextually, will vary from person to person.
Some, certainly, e.g. 'sake', will be learned only contextually.
The same would seem plausible for terms like 'molecule', which, unlike 'red', 'square', and 'tile', do
not refer to things that can be distinctively pointed out. Such terms can, however, be inculcated also
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 14 de 200
by yet a third method: description of the intended objects. This method could be grouped under the
head of the contextual, but it deserves separate notice.
What makes insensible things intelligibly describable is analogy, notably the special form of analogy
known as extrapolation. Thus consider molecules, which are described as smaller than anything seen.
This term 'smaller' is initially meaningful to us through some manner of association with such
observable contrasts as that of a bee to a bird, a gnat to a bee, or a mote of dust to a gnat. The
extrapolation that leads to talk of wholly invisible particles, microbes for example, can be
represented as an analogy of relation: microbes are supposed to compare in size to the motes of dust
as these do to the bees. If microbes elude scrutiny, no wonder; so does the dust most of the time.
Microscopes confirm the doctrine of
-14microbes, but are not at all needed in understanding it; and the descent to yet smaller particles,
molecules and others, taxes the imagination equally little.
Once we have imagined molecules with the help thus of size analogies, we bring other analogies to
bear. Thus, applying dynamical terms first learned in connection with visible things, we represent
molecules as moving, bumping, bouncing. Such is analogy's power to make sense of the insensible.
But analogy in the primary sense, as we might call it, relates things that are already known apart
from the analogy. To say that molecules are conceived by analogy to motes or other observed
particles is evidently to depart from that sense of analogy. If we locate the analogy rather in the
relation of smallerness, as I have done in suggesting that the smallerness relation of molecules or
microbes to motes is understood by analogy to the observed smallerness relation of motes to gnats
and the like, we still depart from analogy in the primary sense; the analogy is still not one between
things (or relations) known apart from the analogy. We can, however, put the matter as an analogy
also in the primary sense. What stand in this analogy are the whole observable solids on the one hand
and observable swarms ordinarily so-called, e.g. of motes or gnats, on the other.
This analogy is of course very limited. A supplementary aid to appreciating the dynamics of the
molecules of a solid is found in the different analogy of a stack of bedsprings. And the fact is that
what one learns of molecules by analogy at all is meager. One must see the molecular doctrine at
work in physical theory to get a proper notion of molecules, and this is not a matter of analogy, nor
of description at all. It is a matter of learning the word contextually as a fragment of sentences which
one learns to bring forth, as wholes under appropriate circumstances.
In the case of some of the terms that refer or purport to refer to physical objects, the value of analogy
is more limited still than in the molecular instance. Thus in the physics of light, with its notoriously
mixed metaphor of wave and particle, the physicist's understanding of what he is talking about must
depend almost wholly on context: on knowing when to use various sentences which speak jointly of
photons and of observed phenomena of light. Such sentences are like cantilever constructions,
anchored in what they say of familiar objects at the near end and supporting the recondite
-15objects at the far end. Explanation becomes oddly reciprocal: photons are posited to help explain the
phenomena, and it is those phenomena and the theory concerning them that explain what the
physicist is driving at in his talk of photons. 1
One tends to imagine that when someone propounds a theory concerning some sort of objects, our
understanding of what he is saying will have two phases: first we must understand what the objects
are, and second we must understand what the theory says about them. In the case of molecules two
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 15 de 200
such phases are somewhat separable, thanks to the moderately good analogies which implement the
first phase; yet much of our understanding of "what the objects are" awaits the second phase. In the
case of the wavicles there is virtually no significant separation; our coming to understand what the
objects are is for the most part just our mastery of what the theory says about them. We do not learn
first what to talk about and then what to say about it.
Picture two physicists discussing whether neutrinos have mass. Are they discussing the same
objects? They agree that the physical theory which they initially share, the preneutrino theory, needs
emendation in the light of an experimental result now confronting them. The one physicist is urging
an emendation which involves positing a new category of particles, without mass. The other is
urging an alternative emendation which involves positing a new category of particles with mass. The
fact that both physicists use the word 'neutrino' is not significant. To discern two phases here, the
first an agreement as to what the objects are (viz. neutrinos) and the second a disagreement as to how
they are (massless or massive), is absurd.
The division between the words that are to be viewed as referring to objects of some sort, and the
words that are not, is not to be drawn on grammatical lines. 'Sake' provided an extreme illustration of
this point. An illustration in another vein is 'centaur'. An illustration in a third vein is 'attribute', there
being philosophical disagreement over whether there are attributes. The question what there is will
be scrutinized later (Ch. VII). But meanwhile we see that the differences in ways of learning words
cut across
____________________
1On the indirectness of the connection between theoretical terms and terms of observation see
Braithwaite, Scientific Explanation, Ch. 3; Carnap, "Methodological character of theoretical
concepts"; Einstein, p. 289; Frank, Ch. 16; Hempel, both works.
-16the grammatical differences and also across the referential ones. 'Centaur', though true of nothing,
will commonly be learned by description of its purported objects. Also of course it could be learned
contextually. 'Sake' can be learned only contextually. 'Tile', which does refer to objects, may be
learned either in isolation as a one-word sentence, or contextually, or by description. 'Molecule',
which also (let us grant) refers to objects, will be learned both contextually and by description.
Similarly for 'photon' and 'neutrino', except that the descriptive factor is less than in the case of
'molecule'. 'Class' and 'attribute', finally, whether or not we grant that they refer to objects, will pretty
surely be learned in context only.
§ 5. EVIDENCE
Words can be learned as parts of longer sentences, and some words can be learned as one-word
sentences through direct ostension of their objects. In either event, words mean only as their use in
sentences is conditioned to sensory stimuli, verbal and otherwise. Any realistic theory of evidence
must be inseparable from the psychology of stimulus and response, applied to sentences.
The pattern of conditioning is complex and inconstant from person to person, but there are points of
general congruence: combinations of questions and non-verbal stimulations which are pretty sure to
elicit an affirmative answer from anyone fit to be numbered within the relevant speech community.
Johnson struck such a combination, putting himself in the way of a stimulus that would trigger an
affirmative response from any of us to the question whether a stone is there.
Calling a stone a stone at close quarters is an extreme case. Evidence is deliberately marshaled only
when there is more nearly an equilibrium between the sensory conditioning of an affirmative
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 16 de 200
response and the contrary conditioning, mediated by the interanimation of sentences. Thus the
question under deliberation may be whether something glimpsed from a moving car was a stone.
That it was a stone, and that it was a crumpled paper, are two ready responses; and the tendency to
the former is inhibited by the tendency to the latter, via sentential interconnections at the level of
common-sense physical theory. Then one "checks," or seeks overwhelming evidence, by returning to
the spot to the best of his judgment and so putting himself in the way of stimulations more
-17firmly and directly associated with the attribution of stonehood or paperhood.
If the thing was glimpsed rather from a moving train, the checking operation may be impracticable.
In this event the question may be left frankly unresolved "for lack of evidence," or, if one cares a lot,
tentatively resolved in the light of any available "circumstantial evidence." Thus if the region next
traversed looks boulderstrewn, and signs of man are scarce, we may guess that the thing was stone
rather than paper. What we are doing when we amass and use circumstantial evidence is to let
ourselves be actuated as sensitively as possible by chain stimulations as they reverberate through our
theory, from present sensory stimulations, via the interanimation of sentences.
Dr. Johnson's affirmative was firmly enough conditioned to the given stimuli, among others, to
withstand any contrary pull via the interanimation of sentences; but in the general case evidence is a
question of center of gravity. Commonly we have to be governed by a delicate balancing of varied
forces transmitted across the fabric of sentences from remotely relevant stimuli. Sometimes this is
because, as in the train, strong stimuli such as Johnson's are inaccessible, or because some fairly
strong one is countered by the combined pull of many lesser forces from across the fabric. And often
it is because the sentence at stake is one that is understood solely through a conditioning of it to other
sentences.
Prediction combines what the car example illustrates with what the train example illustrates. Thus
we may reach a verdict of stonehood by the indirect method of the train example, and still return to
the spot to check. Our prediction is that the ensuing close-range stimulations will be of the sort that
vigorously elicit verdicts of stonehood. Prediction is in effect the conjectural anticipation of further
sensory evidence for a foregone conclusion. When a prediction comes out wrong, what we have is a
divergent and troublesome sensory stimulation that tends to inhibit that once foregone conclusion,
and so to extinguish the sentence-to-sentence conditionings that led to the prediction. Thus it is that
theories wither when their predictions fail.
In an extreme case, the theory may consist in such firmly conditioned connections between sentences
that it withstands the failure of a prediction or two. We find ourselves excusing the failure of
prediction as a mistake in observation or a result of unexplained
-18interference. The tail thus comes, in an extremity, to wag the dog.
The sifting of evidence would seem from recent remarks to be a strangely passive affair, apart from
the effort to intercept helpful stimuli: we just try to be as sensitively responsive as possible to the
ensuing interplay of chain stimulations. What conscious policy does one follow, then, when not
simply passive toward this interanimation of sentences? Consciously the quest seems to be for the
simplest story. Yet this supposed quality of simplicity is more easily sensed than described. Perhaps
our vaunted sense of simplicity, or of likeliest explanation, is in many cases just a feeling of
conviction attaching to the blind resultant of the interplay of chain stimulations in their various
strengths.
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 17 de 200
At any rate, simplicity considerations in some sense may be said to determine even the least
inquisitive observer's most casual acts of individual recognition. For he is continually having to
decide, if only implicitly, whether to construe two particular encounters as repeated encounters with
an identical physical object or as encounters with two distinct physical objects. And he decides in
such a way as to minimize, to the best of his unconscious ability, such factors as multiplicity of
objects, swiftness of interim change of quality and position, and, in general, irregularity of natural
law. 1
The deliberate scientist goes on in essentially the same way, if more adroitly; and a law of least
action remains prominent among his guiding principles. Working standards of simplicity, however
difficult still of formulation, figure ever more explicitly. It is part of the scientist's business to
generalize or extrapolate from sample data, and so to arrive at laws covering more phenomena than
have been checked; and simplicity, by his lights, is just what guides his extrapolation. Simplicity is
of the essence of statistical inference. If his data are represented by points on a graph, and his law is
to be represented by a curve through the points, he draws the smoothest, simplest such curve he can.
He even forces the points a little bit to make it simpler, pleading inaccuracy of measurement. If he
can get a still simpler curve by omitting a few of the plotted points altogether, he tries to account for
them separately.
Simplicity is not a desideratum on a par with conformity to observation. Observation serves to test
hypotheses after adoption; simplicity prompts their adoption for testing. Still, decisive ob____________________
1For a brilliant logical paradigm of this enterprise see Carnap's Aufbau, where he sketches what he
calls the dritte Stufe.
-19servation is commonly long delayed or impossible; and, insofar at least, simplicity is final arbiter.
Whatever simplicity is, it is no casual hobby. As a guide of inference it is implicit in unconscious
steps as well as half explicit in deliberate ones. The neurological mechanism of the drive for
simplicity is undoubtedly fundamental though unknown, and its survival value overwhelming.
One incidental benefit of simplicity that can escape notice is that it tends to enhance a theory's scopeits richness in observable consequences. For, let be a theory, and let C be the class of all the
testable consequences of . The theory q will have been suggested to us by some set K of prior
observations, a subclass of C. In general, the simpler is, the smaller the sample K of C that will
have sufficed to suggest . To say this is just to repeat the earlier remark: that simplicity is what
guides extrapolation. But the relationship can also be described in inverted form: given K, the
simpler is, the more inclusive C will tend to be. Granted, subsequent checking on C may do away
with ; meanwhile the gain in scope is there. 2
Simplicity also engenders good working conditions for the continued activity of the creative
imagination; for, the simpler a theory, the more easily we can keep relevant considerations in mind.
But another quality which is perhaps equally valuable on this score is familiarity of principle.
Familiarity of principle is what we are after when we contrive to "explain" new matters by old laws;
e.g., when we devise a molecular hypothesis in order to bring the phenomena of heat, capillary
attraction, and surface tension under the familiar old laws of mechanics. Familiarity of principle also
figures when "unexpected observations" (i.e., ultimately, some undesirable conflict between sensory
conditionings as mediated by the interanimation of sentences) prompt us to revise an old theory; the
way in which familiarity of principle then figures is in favoring minimum revision.
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 18 de 200
The helpfulness of familiarity of principle for the continuing activity of the creative imagination is a
sort of paradox. Conservatism, a favoring of the inherited or invented conceptual scheme of one's
own previous work, is at once the counsel of laziness and a strategy of discovery. Note, though, the
important normative difference between simplicity and conservatism. Whenever simplicity
____________________
2On the benefits of simplicity see further Kemeny, "The use of simplicity in induction."
-20and conservatism are known to counsel opposite courses, the verdict of conscious methodology is on
the side of simplicity. Conservatism is nevertheless the preponderant force, but no wonder: it can
still operate when stamina and imagination fail.
Yet another principle that may be said to figure as a tacit guide of science is that of sufficient reason.
A lingering trace of this venerable principle seems recognizable, at any rate, in the scientist's
shunning of gratuitous singularities. 3 If he arrives at laws of dynamics that favor no one frame of
reference over others that are in motion with respect to it, he forthwith regards the notion of absolute
rest and hence of absolute position as untenable. This rejection is not, as one is tempted to suppose, a
rejection of the empirically undefinable; empirically unexceptionable definitions of rest are ready to
hand, in the arbitrary adoption of any of various specifiable frames of reference. It is a rejection of
the gratuitous. This principle may, however, plausibly be subsumed under the demand for simplicity,
thanks to the looseness of the latter idea.
§ 6. POSITS AND TRUTH
We may think of the physicist as interested in systematizing such general truths as can be said in
common-sense terms about ordinary physical things. But within this medium the best he achieves is
a combination of ill-connected theories about projectiles, temperature changes, capillary attraction,
surface tension, etc. A sufficient reason for his positing extraordinary physical things, viz. molecules
and subvisible groups of molecules, is that for the thus-supplemented universe he can devise a theory
' which is simpler than and agrees with in its consequences for ordinary things. Its further
consequences for his posited extraordinary things are incidental.
(As it happens, he does a bit better. Besides being simpler than , his ' excels on the score of
familiarity of underlying principles; cf. § 5. Moreover, even those of its consequences that can be
stated in common-sense terms about ordinary things exceed those of , and apparently without
including sentences that there is reason to deny.)
If by some oracle the physicist could identify outright all the truths that can be said in common-sense
terms about ordinary things, still his separation of statements about molecules into true
____________________
3See Birkhoff, Lecture II.
-21and false would remain largely unsettled. We can imagine him partly settling that separation by what
is vaguely called scientific method: by considerations of simplicity of the joint theory of ordinary
things and molecules. But conceivably the truths about molecules are only partially determined by
any ideal organon of scientific method plus all the truths that can be said in commonsense terms
about ordinary things; for in general the simplest possible theory to a given purpose need not be
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 19 de 200
unique.
Actually the truths that can be said even in common-sense terms about ordinary things are
themselves, in turn, far in excess of any available data. The incompleteness of determination of
molecular behavior by the behavior of ordinary things is hence only incidental to this more basic
indeterminacy: both sorts of events are less than determined by our surface irritations. This remains
true even if we include all past, present, and future irritations of all the far-flung surfaces of
mankind, and probably even if we throw in an in fact unachieved ideal organon of scientific method
besides.
Considered relative to our surface irritations, which exhaust our clues to an external world, the
molecules and their extraordinary ilk are thus much on a par with the most ordinary physical objects.
The positing of those extraordinary things is just a vivid analogue of the positing or acknowledging
of ordinary things: vivid in that the physicist audibly posits them for recognized reasons, whereas the
hypothesis of ordinary things is shrouded in prehistory. Though for the archaic and unconscious
hypothesis of ordinary physical objects we can no more speak of a motive than of motives for being
human or mammalian, yet in point of function and survival value it and the hypothesis of molecules
are alike. So much the better, of course, for the molecules.
To call a posit a posit is not to patronize it. A posit can be unavoidable except at the cost of other no
less artificial expedients. Everything to which we concede existence is a posit from the standpoint of
a description of the theory-building process, and simultaneously real from the standpoint of the
theory that is being built. Nor let us look down on the standpoint of the theory as make-believe; for
we can never do better than occupy the standpoint of some theory or other, the best we can muster at
the time.
What reality is like is the business of scientists, in the broadest sense, painstakingly to surmise; and
what there is, what is real, is part of that question. The question how we know what there is is
-22simply part of the question, so briefly contemplated in § 5, of the evidence for truth about the world.
The last arbiter is so-called scientific method, however amorphous.
Scientific method was vaguely seen in § 5 as a matter of being guided by sensory stimuli, a taste for
simplicity in some sense, and a taste for old things. From a study of the considerable literature on
scientific method, a more detailed body of canons could be brought together; though it is customary
to doubt that the thing can be done finally and definitively. At any rate scientific method, whatever
its details, produces theory whose connection with all possible surface irritation consists solely in
scientific method itself, unsupported by ulterior controls. This is the sense in which it is the last
arbiter of truth.
Peirce was tempted to define truth outright in terms of scientific method, as the ideal theory which is
approached as a limit when the (supposed) canons of scientific method are used unceasingly on
continuing experience. 1 But there is a lot wrong with Peirce's notion, besides its assumption of a
final organon of scientific method and its appeal to an infinite process. There is a faulty use of
numerical analogy in speaking of a limit of theories, since the notion of limit depends on that of
"nearer than," which is defined for numbers and not for theories. And even if we by-pass such
troubles by identifying truth somewhat fancifully with the ideal result of applying scientific method
outright to the whole future totality of surface irritations, still there is trouble in the imputation of
uniqueness ("the ideal result"). For, as urged two pages back, we have no reason to suppose that
man's surface irritations even unto eternity admit of any one systematization that is scientifically
better or simpler than all possible others. It seems likelier, if only on account of symmetries or
dualities, that countless alternative theories would be tied for first place. Scientific method is the way
file://E:\Incoming\quine.1960.word_and_object.html
28/4/2007
Página 20 de 200
to truth, but it affords even in principle no unique definition of truth. Any so-called pragmatic
definition of truth is doomed to failure equally.
After that reflection, there may be some consolation in the following one. If there were (contrary to
what we just concluded) an unknown but unique best total systematization of science conformable
to the past, present, and future nerve-hits of mankind, so that we might define the whole truth as that
unknown , still we
____________________
1Peirce, vol. 5, paragraph 407.
-23should not thereby have defined truth for actual single sentences. We could not say, derivatively, that
any single sentence S is true if it or a translation belongs to , for there is in general no sense in
equating a sentence of a theory with a sentence S given apart from . Unless pretty firmly and
directly conditioned to sensory stimulation, a sentence S is meaningless except relative to its own
theory; meaningless intertheoretically. 2 This point, already pretty evident from § 3 and from the
parable of neutrinos in § 4, will be developed in more detail in Chapter II.
It is rather when we turn back into the midst of an actually present theory, at least hypothetically
accepted, that we can and do speak sensibly of this and that sentence as true. Where it makes sense
to apply 'true' is to a sentence couched in the terms of a given theory and seen from within the